The second argument to which
the soi-disant defenders of religious freedom resort, is the appeal to “conscience;”
without, however, actually displaying any. What do we mean by submission to the
commands of conscience? One of the most well-known of all historical examples
answers the question with clarity: In 1942 in Vichy France, in the Huguenot
town of Chambon-sur-Lignon, Pastor Andre Trocme preached a sermon to his
parishioners, in which he exhorted them to give shelter, despite the danger
they would incur, to Jews fleeing the deportations, “lest innocent blood be
shed.” In the next three years 5000 Jews passed through or were sheltered in
the town; not a single one was ever betrayed to the Vichy police or the
Gestapo. Years later, asked by an interviewer why his family harbored Jews
knowing that execution awaited anyone caught doing that, a peasant farmer
shrugged his shoulders uncomfortably and replied, “someone in trouble comes to
your door–what can you do?” To act from conscience, in other words, is not to
submit to the commands of a coercive or threatening authority (unlike Catholic
Bishops, Pastor Trocme had no ecclesiastical power over his congregation); nor
merely to follow unswervingly the rules
of whatever association you belong to: Sandy Koufax was being a good Jew but
not following conscience when he refused to pitch in a World Series game on Yom
Kippur. Rather it is willingly to put ones own self in jeopardy in order to
protect, or avoid doing harm to, or secure justice for, others. (In fact, those
who’ve investigated conscientious resistance during the Holocaust--e.g.,
Kristin Monroe and Norman Geras--have found no correlation between acts of
resistance and religious belief.)
Recently, for example, the Vatican reprimanded and demanded submission
from an organization of American Catholic nuns, who were charged with promoting
“radical feminism” and having “serious doctrinal problems,” due to their
support of the poor and marginalized. In other words, they have been acting in
accordance with their consciences, and have been commanded to cease and desist.
So much for “conscience:”
it is a rare Catholic
physician indeed who has to fear sanction for refusing to perform an abortion–or
to prescribe birth control pills.
As for the argument that religious ethics ontologically
stand upon a higher ground, or what is sometimes called the “divine command
theory” of ethics, it is not only dogmatic but also self-contradictory, in that its force is
contingent upon the existence of one true religion. If there is not one true
religion but rather there are conflicting theistic versions of the Good and the
True--conflicting divine commands--then to invoke “religious principles”
against a particular instance of coercion is at the same time to deny the
religious principles of those who favor that kind of coercion, or who simply
favor the toleration of a plurality of different belief systems. Should Jehovah’s
Witnesses go to jail for refusing to register for the draft, while Catholic
gynecologists and priests should be rewarded with praise for refusing to allow
the prescription of abortifacients by health care plans that receive direct or
indirect public subsidy? Should Islamists who believe, correctly or not, that
fidelity to the Koran compels honor killings or retaliatory rapes, be indulged
for engaging in those practices? Given that religion is by nature based on
faith and not observable facts, there is no simple resolution to the brute fact
of two religions or religious variants having differing moral codes. Moreover,
the pejorative distinction that the godly always make between their reasoning
and that of their allegedly “secular” opponents is merely self-serving. Anyone
can claim to be doing what god wills; or can insist, the way Unitarians or
Friends or various liberal Protestants might do, that in their conception of
things “god” in fact has the values associated by theocrats with secular
humanism.
On the other hand, if there is but one true religion, one
unerrant set of moral rules, then theocracy is being institutionalized, and the
one true church has implicitly declared war on all of those of us who do not
follow its precepts. There may be reasoned arguments, e.g., against abortion–that
personhood begins at conception, that the fetus feels pain–but they stand or
fall on their strength as arguments. They are no stronger because they are said
to be god-given, and perhaps even weaker, in that when implemented through
legislation by a numerically dominant voice the high ground of principle
becomes merely the amoral stance of might makes right. If having the most votes
to coerce others is the goal of debate, then the ethical high ground has
already been ceded. In the real world of political action, even abortion is
like any other object of political determination: it is not outlawed because it
is wrong, it is wrong because it is outlawed. In any event, all arguments from
inerrancy of scripture or ecclesiastical authority raise the epistemological
question of how anyone comes to know the will of God, and why any of us should
believe that someone else’s scriptures reveal anything of the kind.
Furthermore, few if any religions can claim to be based on texts that detail
their deity's will concerning every possible situation. These gaps often
concern situations that the writers of ancient religious scriptures couldn't
have foreseen, such as those involving advanced technologies, especially
biological and medical ones. In this respect scripturalism is much like
constitutional originalism: it reads our own present interpretations into the
minds of other beings, or in this case non-beings, whose otherness to us is
both total, and totally opaque. Any of us making an ethical case may call on
endless witnesses from heaven or earth, but there is still no more in the end
than the person making that case, just like every other person who makes an
ethical case.
Thus arguments purporting to
rest on the high ground of principle or conscience based on religious doctrine
or membership in a religious association are either arbitrarily self-serving,
dogmatic, or self-contradictory. They deserve neither more nor less credence
than any contrary principle based on any equally cogent set of assertions. At
this point though the theocrats make their final stand on the alternative high
ground of the First Amendment to the American Constitution: “Congress shall
make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free
exercise thereof...”
All of us, though (except perhaps Catholic bishops) know
what the “free exercise of religion” consists of: the right to state one’s
religious beliefs, to congregate together to “exercise” or live by them, to
pray in public, to proselytize others. It not only does not mean but could not
conceivably mean the “right” to do, in the public sphere, whatever one feels
like doing, whether or not contrary to legitimately established public law,
because according to your religion that’s the right thing to do, and contrary
behavior is wrongful. To be sure, the Supreme Court has held on various
occasions (not always without dissent) that there certainly is and ought to be
a private sphere into which the State cannot be allowed to intrude. The State,
e.g., cannot force Catholic women to purchase birth control aids (most of them
will do so in any event), nor prohibit women in general from doing so (ditto).
It also cannot force women to have abortions; nor–though this obvious corollary
is under threat from the Church and its allies–prohibit them from doing
so. These invasions of privacy the
Church is happy to see enforced. But whether such items must be included in
public or publicly subsidized health care packages, is no more or less a matter
of “the free exercise of religion” than any determination about “public health:”
the person who doesn’t want to use them doesn’t have to, and if he doesn’t want
others to use them, that’s none of his business until and unless public law
makes it his business. The only argument the Church attempts to make in this
context is that if it self-insures its employees, it is not acting “publicly.”
But that’s perverse: there would be no health insurance of any kind without the
full panoply of public policies, commands, and exemptions that make it possible
in the first place.
In sum, that leading the life you want to lead can
consist of preventing other people from leading the life they want to lead is
not a principle of religious freedom; it is rather, as John Stuart Mill put it,
“so monstrous a principle” as any that exists. It is the end of religious
freedom.
4 comments:
How do you conclude that Sandy Koufax was not following his conscience? Because he was following Jewish law? Was he following the law because of fear of retribution or because conscience, for him, led him to decide in favor of the law? If conscience were always and only on the side of law-breaking, no law would be possible. I believe this is consistent with a Kantian position.
Is this a fair statement of your own position—that freedom of conscience cannot and should not be limited to religious scruples and that, moreover, one person’s conscience may not bind another’s freedom?
I'm sorry, PJ, I wrote an extensive reply to you, but then lost it while being hopelessly confused trying to sign in and publish it, and just can't go through it again. In short, breaking law not necessary, choices of serious weight necessary, just earning plaudits from your religious community at no cost not act of conscience. Koufax--interesting question, would want to ask him!
JVS Group vape store terdekat lost vape pod vape vape store liquid vape toko vape terdekat harga vape vape pod coil vape mod vape vapor vapor terdekat vapor kecil Vape Store Terdekat vapor blasting vapor adalah vapor murah toko vapor terdekat dari lokasi saya harga vapor vapor storm vapor pod toko vapor terdekat vape store terdekat vape store vape store terdekat dari lokasi saya vape store jakarta vape murah harga vape murah berkualitas mod vape murah pod vape murah vape murah berkualitas vape murah bagus harga vape murah pod kuy pod pod kuy caliburn pod vinci pod kit pod caliburn aflo pod harga pod pod vape aegis pod pod terbaik 2021 pod terbaik pod aegis pod kuy harga pod stick pod drag harga pod kuy foom pod vape pod vinci pod pod murah pod eazy pod adalah relx pod harga pod smok pod drag s lanyard pod liquid yang cocok untuk pod harga pod vinci pod chocolate drag s pod pod smok pod argus cartridge pod drag pod apa itu pod pod aegis boost pod aio pod exceed grip pod vinci pod caliburn g gorilla pod pod oxva pod mod terbaik 2021 cartridge pod kuy pod deddy corbuzier harga pod caliburn cartridge kuy pod
A vape starter kit UK Alecrtofag is a set of vaping tools and equipment designed for beginners in the UK who want to start vaping. It typically includes a vape pen or mod, a battery, a tank, replacement coils, and other accessories. The kit usually comes with instructions about how to use the device, the proper way to fill and refill the tank, how to clean and maintain the atomizer, and how to adjust the wattage and temperature settings. It also includes safety tips, such as not to overcharge the battery and not to leave the device unattended while charging.
Post a Comment