[As I begin this fourth part of my tutorial on Kant's
ethical theory, I am forced to confront once more the fact that there is vastly
more to be said than can be squeezed into even the most capacious
tutorial. I shall try not to make too
great a shambles of it.]
The core idea underlying Kant's analysis, about which we
must be very clear, is the distinction between what we may call behavior and action. By behavior, I mean
any physical movements [including speech, of course, as a physical movement of
the larynx, etc.] that a human being exhibits.
This is a tricky matter, because to be completely clear, we would have
to decide whether we mean to include as behavior physical movements whose proper
description makes essential reference to social meanings -- a bit of behavior
such as giving a command, for example, or playing a game. But assuming that we can sort all that out, all
behavior, on Kant's view, is causally determined. This follows directly from the Second Analogy
teaching that to be real in the Realm of Appearances just is to stand in thoroughgoing causal relationship to what has
gone before and what comes after. Because
behavior is causally determined [and hence, Kant thinks, at least in theory
totally predictable], it is morally neutral.
A bit of human behavior cannot be characterized as either virtuous or
vicious, good or bad. It simply is.
By action, on the other hand, I mean things done by agents
[human or otherwise] in accordance with and because of reasons. [There is a very useful discussion of this
distinction in an old book by the English philosopher R. G. Collingwood. See The
Idea of History.] To act, according
to Kant, is to be guided by reasons.
Now, all reasons are in their logical structure general, not
particular. [This is, of course, totally
independent of whether they are good or bad reasons.] If I choose to do something for a reason, I
implicitly commit myself to a subjectively general rule concerning all other
cases that are like this one in the relevant ways. Kant calls such subjective rules maxims.
It follows, on his view, that whenever we act, we do so in accordance
with a maxim of action. Maxims, as we
shall see, have the syntactic form of imperatives. Generally speaking, they are of the
form: "Having as your goal or
purpose G, do A."
Kant has the reputation of being a rather rigid and rigoristic
moralist, very much an old school Puritanical prig. His teaching about maxims feeds into this
stereotype. We can just imagine him, in
every situation, pausing to ask himself, "What is the maxim of my action?"
before doing anything at all. Not at all
a swinger, let alone a Dionysian! Now,
leaving to one side the fact that as a young man Kant had something of a
reputation as a billiards player and bon
vivant [no kidding], this reflects a fundamental misunderstanding of Kant's
position. The point is that action, as
opposed to behavior, is brought about by reasons rather than causes, and
reasons, by their logical structure, are implicitly general, hence expressible
in the form of maxims. Whether we pause
sententiously to reflect on our reasons or act seemingly spontaneously, it
remains true that insofar as we are acting,
we are determining ourselves by reasons.
The central question of the Grundlegung, and for Kant of all moral philosophy, is whether there
are any subjective maxims that all rational agents as such necessarily adopt as
the rules of their action, simply in virtue of being rational agents. If there are, then those subjective maxims
will be Objective Laws, binding on all rational agents regardless of their
desires, sentiments, purposes, or other differentiating characteristics. If there is one such objective maxim from
which all other objective maxims can be derived, then it will be The Moral
Law. Its validity for us will be
absolutely unconditional. That, in a
nutshell, is what Kant is looking for in his moral philosophy. Anything less, in his view, does not deserve
to be called moral philosophy at all.
If you are paying very close attention, it may occur to you
that there is a really big problem here.
Action takes place in the Realm of Appearance just as much as behavior
does. Kant thinks, for example, that I
am morally obligated to keep my promises, [more of this when we get to Section
Two.] Now, a promise is a commitment
made by one person to another person in
the Realm of Appearance. The keeping
[or breaking] of the promise also occurs in the Realm of Appearance. But since both the making and the keeping [or
breaking] of the promise occur in the Realm of Appearance, they must be bits of
behavior standing in thoroughgoing causal relation to everything else that
happens. How on earth can the making of
a promise be both a bit of behavior
falling under universal causal laws and also
an action undertaken in accordance with a maxim?
This is a simply huge problem, to which Kant devotes Section
Three of the Grundlegung, and about
which we shall have a very great deal to say.
A second point of information and clarification before we
turn to the Three Propositions listed at the end of Part Three above. Because Kant is searching for rules of action
that are binding on all rational agents as such, he conceives these rules as
equally valid for non-human rational agents as well, which to him meant
angels. [No snarky laughter please. If it makes you more comfortable, substitute
aliens for angels] Our human condition
-- our desire for pleasure, our aversion to pain, our mortality, our talents,
sentiments, and predilections -- are all, from Kant's point of view, limitations or constraints on our nature
as rational agents. Because of them, we
have difficulty obeying The Moral Law, and find ourselves tempted to ignore it. Hence, we experience the Moral Law as an
unconditional command, a Categorical Imperative. But it is at least possible that there should
be rational agents unconstrained in this fashion, who recognize the objective
validity of the Moral Law and abide by it simply because it is dictated by the
universal principles of rationality.
Such beings, Kant sometimes says, possess a Holy Will. They do not experience the Moral Law as a
command, because they are not tempted to disobey it.
I find it interesting to compare this to the rules of formal
logic, such as the Law of Contradiction. Mathematicians do not find themselves
tempted to break the Law of Contradiction, secretly asserting "p and not
p" when no one is looking, or wondering whether they can get away with an
argument cast in one of the invalid syllogistic forms [Some A are B; some B are
C; therefore Some A are C, for example.]
If I may speak somewhat oddly, all of us, as mathematicians or
logicians, have a holy will when it comes to reasoning in those disciplines. That is what it would be like to have a Holy
Will in general.
By the way, there are lovely echoes here of the New Testament
teaching that those reborn in Christ act naturally and spontaneously in
conformity with the Law, as laid down in the Old Testament. Paul, of course, had some difficulty with
several of the communities of followers of Jesus, who were doing some rather
hinky things in the belief that, as reborn, they could do no wrong. He put a stop to that nonsense, I am happy to
say. :)
Well, enough of throat clearing. Next part, I will address the three
propositions directly.
Less snarky--whether God or Jesus is a non-human rational agent (upon which hangs the question of whether one or the other is the king of the kingdom of ends).
ReplyDelete