Originally, as we have just seen, economists presumed that all indices,
including rents, were determined by the interplay of objective factors
(facility of production, fertility of land, and so forth) as these are taken up
into the rational calculations of profit-maximizing agents. The calculability
of economic magnitudes -- the possibility, that is, of deducing the magnitude
of changes in prices, rents, wages, or profits that would result from a change
in a technique of production, say, -- depends completely on this assumption of
rational self-interest. In order to determine the effect of an improvement in
the technique for producing corn, for example, we must assume that corn
producers will adopt the new technique unhesitatingly once they calculate that
it is more profitable; that consumers will bid down the price of corn as soon
as there is excess supply in the market; that producers in less profitable
lines will shift their capital as soon as possible to the corn sector, where
higher profits are being made; and that landlords will readily rent out their
land for as much as or as little as they can get.
With these assumptions, some very nice theoretical deductions can be
made. For example, with the aid of modern mathematical techniques, it can be
shown that any technological innovation that it is profitable for the
individual firm to introduce at current prices will, once the total system of
prices has adjusted itself to the innovation, have the effect of raising the
system-wide rate of profit. Or, to take a very much more elegant and powerful
result due to the great mathematician John von Neumann, any economy engaged
solely in the production of capital goods and wage goods has available to it a
balanced growth path along which the growth rate of the economy exactly equals
the profit rate. And so on and on.
Once we introduce Mill’s factor of custom, however, all such deductions
become in principle impossible. If the rental for land depends in part upon
custom and habit, what will be the effect on rents of an improvement in the
techniques for producing corn? If custom is not a factor, the answer is simple:
rents will rise. With a little modern algebra, one can even calculate exactly
how much they will rise. But if custom is a factor, there is really no
telling. The most we can possibly say is that if custom holds sway, rents may
change not at all. If competition is the sole determinant, the full effect will
be felt. Somewhere between the two lies the answer.
Now, growth depends on the disposition of the annual surplus, and
according to the behavioral assumptions of the classical model, capitalists
invest and landlords consume. So clearly the secondary effect of custom will be
to alter the growth rate of the economy. The more custom operates to hold rents
at the traditional levels in the face of technical advances in corn production,
the more will the additional output resulting from those advances turn up as
profit in the pockets of the capitalists, there to serve as additional capital
for growth. The less custom operates, the more additional output will end up as
increased rents, to be consumed unproductively by the profligate landlords.
How can we adjust our theory to take account of custom? The obvious
maneuver, and the one which is essentially at the heart of modern econometrics,
is to introduce into our equations a dummy variable standing for the influence
of custom on rents. We can, for example, stipulate that when techniques of corn
production change, the rents will change by a factor of k times the amount that
would change if competition along were operative.
The value of k, obviously, cannot be calculated by the sort of a priori
reasoning on which classical theory rests. In order to put a value to k, it
would be necessary for us to collect large amounts of data from actual
land-rentals over long periods of time. We would then have to make a number of
simplifying assumptions, such as that all renters are affected by custom to the
same degree, that the effect of custom is reasonably constant over time, and so
on.
Now, it is very important to understand that this something called
custom which is thereby introduced into our model has an ontological status if
you will permit me some heavy philosophical artillery, fundamentally different
from that of the rational self-interest underlying competition. “Custom” is not
that name of a principle of rational choice, nor is it even the name of a
stable, identifiable non-rational psychological element. “Custom” is simply a
catch-all title for the sum-total of all the deviations from rational
self-interest that might cause ground-rents to be something other than what the
pure theory of competition dictates. Some landlords may fail to adjust rents
because of laziness, others because of stubbornness, others for religious or
family reasons, and others still because of bonds of baronial loyalty to the
peasantry. Obviously, a wide variety of historical, social, economic, and
cultural forces may manifest themselves under the heading of custom, with
economic consequences of quite varied sorts.
With the marginalist revolution of the 1870’s, based on the substitution
of subjective utility for objective technology as the fundamental determinant
of price, all hope is given up of a theoretically a priori determination of
economic magnitudes. Individual consumers are assumed to have consistent
preferences among alternative bundles of commodities, but these preferences --
summarized under the heading “utility functions” -- are asvaried, as
idiosyncratic, and as unfathomable as any subjective psychological phenomena
can be. Economists have sought to overcome the anarchy of subjective preference
by a number of heroic assumptions about the general mathematical shape of
individual indices of satisfaction -- assumptions that bear no particular
relation to reality. The result is an elegant structure of microeconomic theory
-- what is now called the theory of consumer behavior -- whose principal virtue
is its ability to support the ideological claim that capitalism is both
efficient and fair. What has been lost, however, is the ability to relate the
objective facts of technology and production in some direct way to the
structure of prices, wages, profits, and rents through which the social product
is distributed among the major classes of the society. It is in fact quite
striking that the original theoretical model of equilibrium put forward by Leon
Walras is actually a model of pure barter or exchange, in which production does
not figure at all. Only after he has established his major theoretical propositions
for the case of an exchange economy in which the goods being exchanged are
simply posited, or given, at the outset, can Walras move on to extend his
theory to the case of production.
The central theoretical claim of marginalism, of course, was that a capitalist
economy, unfettered by state restrictions or legal distortions, would achieve
and maintain an equilibrium position in which all markets, including the market
for labour, would clear and in which no further improvement in subjective
satisfaction could be achieved by mutually acceptable exchanges. To say that
the labour market clears is to say that there is no long-term involuntary
unemployment. Those who are out of work are either between jobs, as it were, or
else prefer leisure to employment on the terms being offered.
The equilibrium thesis of marginalism was mortally wounded by the
experience of the great depression. The presence of millions of unemployment
workers, unable to find work year after year, constituted as much refutation as
any scientist could want of the theses of the established economic theories. It
was clear that the microeconomic foundations of economic theory were incapable
of yielding plausible macroeconomic conclusions. There were two options open to
the economist: the first was the reject the microeconomic foundations, and
begin a search for a theoretical perspective capable of yielding conclusions
more in keeping with reality. The second was to formulate a theory of the
economy as a whole, and leave to one side, at least for the time, the relation
of the large scale theory to the theory of individual economic units. As you
all know, John Maynard Keynes’ GENERAL THEORY took the second tack.
I do not propose today to review Keynes’ theory. Rather, I wish to call
attention to certain of its foundations which tend to be lost sight of in the
complications and elaborations of macroeconomic model-building. Essentially
what Keynes does is to extend and generalize Mill’s notion of custom by
introducing into his analysis of the behavior of capitalists and workers the
idea of subjective preference and subjective estimates of probability.
The most dramatic break with previous economic theory was the
substitution of subjective expectation for objective probabilities or perfect
knowledge. It is, on reflection, obvious that what actually determines a
capitalist’s decisions is his subjective estimate of future prices, future
sales, future costs, not the actual prices, sales, and costs that ensue.
Keynes, who was methodologically quite sophisticated about matters of rational
choice and probability, therefore constructs his entire model of investment and
employment on the basis of such subjective estimates of probability, or, as he
calls them, expectations.
At the same time, Keynes loosens up the classical behavioral assumptions
by recognizing that capitalists are not perfect accumulators and workers are
not perfect consumers. Instead, each individual is thought of as having a
certain innate psychological inclination or propensity to consume some
proportion of his or her available income. When it comes to disposing of the
remainder of the income, the individual is conceived as having a second
propensity or subjective preference, namely a preference for holding a certain
proportion of the non-consumed income in the form of money, the remainder to be
invested.
This positing of psychological propensities and preferences is in
keeping with a long tradition of British empiricist thinking, which goes all
the way back to the writings of David Hume, Lord Shaftesbury, and Frances
Hutcheson. Like his distinguished predecessors, Keynes is essentially an
armchair psychologist, offering quasi – a priori reasoning rather than
experimental evidence in support of his claims about human motivation.
Here, for example, is Keynes introducing one of the building-blocks of
his theory:
"The fundamental psychological law, upon which we are
entitled to depend with great confidence both a priori from our knowledge of
human nature and from the detailed facts of experience, is that men are
disposed, as a rule and on average, to increase their consumption as their
income increases, but not by as much as the increase in their income." (Keynes, p.96)
Keynes then offers a mathematical expression of this so-called “law”
which makes it look quite impressive and objective, but obviously we have here
nothing more than an ad hoc stipulation.
The central concept of Keynes’ analytical model is what he calls the
“marginal efficiency of capital.” He defines this, in a manner familiar to
those who have studied some economics as follows:
“the relation between the prospective yield of one more unit (of a
certain type of capital) and the cost of producing that unit.”
The key word in this definition, though it may not seem so, is “prospective.”
The cost of producing one more unit of machinery, is objectively determined by
the current state of technology in the machinery-producing industry taken
together with the current costs for steel, coal, labour, and so forth. In
short, the cost of producing one more unit of machinery, or of any other sort
of capital, is the sort of objective fact that classical economics dealt in.
But the prospective yield of that additional unit is quite another matter.
“Prospective yield” simply means “yield expected by the capitalist making the
investment.” If his hopes are high, his animal spirits frisky, then he will
evaluate the prospects for future yield quite favorably, and as a consequence
the marginal efficiency of the capital will be high. If, with exactly the same
technology available and the same current prices ruling in the market, he takes
a gloomy view of the future, anticipating a downturn, dreading the turn of
international affairs, fearing a resurgence of the Labour Party and a decline
of the Tories, then the marginal efficiency of capital will decline.
These remarks are in no sense an exposé of the hidden and unacknowledged
implications of Keynes’ theories. Quite to the contrary, he is insistant to the
point of repetition on the subjective sources of economic indices. “It is
evident,” he says at one point in his discussion of the incentives to
liquidity, “that the rate of interest is a highly psychological phenomenon.”
(p. 202). And when he comes to restate his general theory, he lists among his
ultimate variables “the three fundamental psychological factors, namely, the
psychological propensity to consume, the psychological attitude to liquidity
and the psychological expectation of future yield from capital-assets,” which
is to say, the propensity to consume, liquidity preference, and the marginal
efficiency of capital.
4 comments:
Key phrase--"assumptions that bear no particular relation to reality." And, yet, society continues to labor under them.
Thanks for these articles. As a PhD student (economics, at UMass Amherst) I appreciate this take on Keynes. At a time when everyone likes to think of Keynes as simply someone who thought that Aggregate Demand mattered and that fiscal policy was effective, it's good to see a richer appreciation of his views.
I look forward to seeing how this discussion fits into a critique of Keynes. Thanks again!
I feel like this essay is only half done. Where is part 3?
The essay rehearses well-known problems with classical and neo-classical economics (by its own admission, the essay's summary is "scarcely original"), but the essay doesn't show that these problems are fatal or, more important, that they pave the way for a more promising approach to economics which supports socialism (the proof of which is the essay's avowed goal).
This third part has its work cut out for it.
Reply to Chris Langston: You are quite correct that the essay needs that third part. I must say, by the way, that I am always a trifle suspicious about off-hand descriptions of the criticisms of a widely held position as "well-known," especially when nobody shows much interest in taking them seriously and moving beyond the received wisdom to something quite different. I think a case can be made for moving beyond neo-classical theory to a theory of socialism [see my essay, The Future of Socialism, for some suggestions]. But these days we seem to be moving rapidly backwards to economic theories that neo-classical theory was intended to supplant. If I can perhaps inspire some young hotshot to undertake the development of a modern defense of socialism, in the context of capitalism as it now exists, I will be quite happy to subside into old age and let him or her take the lead.
Post a Comment