Consider this several part essay as an inadequate reply to Magpie's request for some comments about commodity money.
In this essay, I undertake to follow in the footsteps of
Wile E. Coyote, the immortal antagonist in the Road Runner animated cartoons
who, in episode after episode, races madly over the edge of a cliff, suspended
for several steps by his sheer momentum, stops, looks down, realizes there is
nothing under him, gets a look of chagrin on his face, and plummets to
earth. I am going to launch a
several-part rumination on money, fully aware that I do not know how to bring
it to a satisfactory conclusion. For several
days, it will seem that I am proceeding confidently toward a goal that is
surely clear to me even if not to my readers, only at some point down the road
to pause, notice that my argument lacks grounding, get whatever passes in the
blogosphere for a look of chagrin [surely there is an emoticon for that],
whereupon I shall plummet to earth. Why
am I doing this? Wile E. at least is
blessed with restorative amnesia, so each of his crashes is, from his point of
view, his first. But though I am ancient,
approaching my eightieth birthday, I can still recall what it is like to follow
an argument all the way to its conclusion.
My reason is simple: I am hopeful
that when I pull up short and look down, one of you will hold out a hand, catch
me, and offer a continuation of the argument beyond the point to which I am
able to carry it.
In the simplest case, at the end of each cycle of
production, each producer holds some non-zero quantity of the single commodity
produced in his industry. There then
ensues an interval of exchange before the next cycle of production
commences. Each producer exchanges a
portion of his gross output [possibly all of it] for the inputs required for
another round of production at the same level of activity. The remainder, if there be any, is exchanged
for some market basket [or vector if we are being mathematical] of surplus
outputs which he consumes unproductively [on a lavish lifestyle, perhaps, or on
an extension of his library of theology books.]
For an economy of a given size [the specification of which
is actually a problem, once we treat labor as a produced commodity], there
exists some vector of positive industry activity levels that guarantees a
clearing of all markets at the prices determined by the technical coefficients
of production, by a zero rate of return in the labor-producing industry, and by
a uniform rate of profit in the rest of the economy. All of this can be stated using a variety of
symbols with superscripts and subscripts in elegant fashion. I shan't try your patience by putting this on
the page [thereby saving myself the effort of introducing Greek letters,
subscripts, and superscripts in Microsoft Word which is a royal pain.]
Nothing essential is altered in this system by the emergence
of a single commodity, such as gold, that functions as commodity money. So long as gold is a produced commodity [as
it is], its ratio of exchange with other commodities will be determined by the
technical coefficients of production, together with the condition of a uniform
rate of return in all sectors save for the labor producing sector, in which a
zero rate of return rules.
As soon as we undertake to introduce the concept of paper
money, or bills of exchange, we are forced to recognize a certain inadequacy in
our previous analysis. We have been
speaking of the exchange of commodities as though capitalist A stands with a
bolt of cloth in his arms, Capitalist B with a bushel basket of wheat in his,
so that at a signal from the director of exchange they physically exchange
burdens and turn about to look for new trading partners. But of course nothing like this is
intended. In the image of physical
exchange, we have suppressed the essential legal framework of exchange, and with it the central legal facts
of ownership, entitlement, and alienation.
In so doing, we have significantly misrepresented the truly social nature of exchange [and
production] relations. At this point, we
must bring these features explicitly into our discussion, for without them we
have no hope of making sense of the phenomena of money and capital.
Let us begin with the notion of an economic agent's ownership of a commodity. It is the law that defines the social/legal
category of economic agent. An economic agent is whoever, or whatever,
may stand in a relationship of ownership
to whatever or whomever is defined as an ownable and alienable good. A person can be an economic agent, but so too
can a corporation, or an animal, or -- if the law so decides -- a tree or a
river. "Economic agent" is
thus an ascriptive term, not a descriptive term. "X is an economic agent" ascribes a
status to X in a system of legal relationships.
The agency legally empowered to decide whether or not a candidate for
the status of economic agent possesses that status [which is to say the judge,
or occupier of a bureaucratically defined office, or jury, or whatever] does
not discover that X is an economic agent, but instead decides that X is an economic agent, by
ascribing that status to X in accordance with the appropriate procedures and
conformity with the applicable laws or regulations. In like manner, "X owns a" ascribes
to X [and to a] a certain legal status, which includes or carries with it a
variety of legal rights and duties concerning a [and other agents, goods, etc.,
possibly.]
1 comment:
Prof.
Much appreciated. I look forward to your exposition!
Post a Comment