Those of you who have been following the comments section
will know that several commentators and I have been discussing the Sokal affair
and the response by Stanley Fish, who was at the time the General Editor under whom
the journal Social Text fell [but not
the editor of that journal itself, as one commentator somewhat inaccurately asserted.] While taking my daily walk yesterday morning
[which was enlivened by sightings of two Blue Herons, two deer, and a rabbit!],
I had an extended conversation with an imaginary audience [my preferred mode of
thinking] in which I attempted to set the Sokal flap in a larger context. It occurred to me that some of you might have
some interest in what I was thinking.
[This is, of course, the operational hubris
on which blogging is premised. It has a
rather uncomfortable similarity to Anthony Weiner's narcissistic sexting, as I
am all too aware. But then, that is a
subject for another day.]
Let me begin in 1620 with Francis Bacon's publication of the
Novum Organum [right away, you can
see this is going to take a while, but then, it is a long walk.] Bacon laid out a method of investigating nature
that consisted, essentially, in making long lists of observations, organizing
them into what he called tables of presence and absence, increase and decrease,
and then using them to check hypotheses about the nature of natural phenomena. For example, if I wanted to figure out what
heat is, I would first make a list of all the hot things I could think of [soup
boiling on a stove, a stone sitting in the noonday sun, my forehead after a
vigorous workout, etc.] and all the cold things I could think of [a piece of
ice, my feet after a long walk in snow, and so forth], and then collect observations
of cases in which something is felt to heat up or cool down. Then I might try out an hypothesis: heat is the presence in an object of blood. Well, that works for my forehead after a vigorous
walk, but it does not work for a pot of boiling soup. So that hypothesis is rejected. You get the idea.
This scientific method had a number of very interesting and
important implications. Consider just three, which were vigorously contested
by some of Bacon's contemporaries, such as Descartes. First:
the right way to learn about nature is to observe it with the senses, by
looking at it, listening to it, touching
it, even tasting it; Second, there is an
absolute differentiation between the observations we make of nature and the
theories we formulate to explain nature -- the theories are, as we would say
but Bacon did not, theory neutral; and Third, scientific knowledge is, by its
very nature, ever-expanding, ever growing, because the collection of observations
keeps getting bigger, and no old observations ever have to be thrown away, even though we keep
discarding theories as more observations allow us to eliminate them.
This picture of science as a succession of theoretical
explanations of an ever-expanding store of observations remained the dominant
understanding of science for a very long time, although it was significantly
altered and revised by three developments:
The first was the invention of instruments [microscope, telescope, x-ray
machine, etc etc] that rapidly expanded and also changed the nature of the
observations. With these instruments, we
could gain information about things that were not apparent to the senses, such as
microbes, distant stars, atomic particles.
It required both equipment and extensive training even to make these
observations, quite apart from the formulation of theories based on them. The second development was the mathematicization
of scientific explanation and theorizing, which altered the sorts of things
that scientists attempted to observe.
The third development, which somewhat undermined the original sharp
distinction between observation and theory, was the slow realization that some
of the states of affairs being observed could not even be described without
assuming the correctness of certain theories.
One could, to be sure, report an experiment simply as the hearing of a
certain number of clicking sounds being produced by a Geiger Counter. But that report was scientifically useless, as an observation, unless it was interpreted
as an indication of the presence of a certain number of sub-atomic particles. But that interpretation necessarily
presupposed both a theory of the atom and a theory of the nature of sub-atomic
particles, theories which it was supposed to be the role of the observations to
confirm or disconfirm.
Despite these developments, whose full implications, of
course, are quite far-reaching, the central conviction remained unchanged that
science is an ever-expanding body of knowledge and explanation resting on an
ever-growing accumulation of observations.
Enter Thomas Kuhn, who in 1962 called this story into
question with the publication of the
Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
If we take a close look at the
actual history of the development of modern science, Kuhn argued, we see that
it does not exhibit that slow, steady growth that the standard account would
lead us to expect. Instead, we see long
periods of what he labeled "normal science," during which things
progress incrementally as we would expect, punctuated by brief upheavals during
which everything changes rapidly and radically -- scientific revolutions, Kuhn
called them. What happens during these
moments of revolutionary transformation is that the old, settled way of
conducting scientific investigations is replaced by a new model, a striking new
experiment or bit of explanation that comes to serve as a new paradigm. When this happens, the bright young scientists
latch onto the new paradigm and imitate it, doing science in a new way. The established scientists, by and large, are
not refuted or proven wrong, and most of them go on doing science as they
always have. But they die out and do not
reproduce themselves, because all the young hotshots are enraptured with the
new paradigm. After a while, things
settle down, and normal science goes on, but now along the lines of the new
paradigm.
A word about "paradigm," which has become a
buzzword in modern discussions but is almost always misunderstood. A paradigm is a concrete specific instance
that serves as a model for imitation. The
most familiar example comes from the Judeo-Christian tradition. In the Old Testament, we read that God handed
down to Moses the Law, which Jews were enjoined to obey and to follow. The Law was not a paradigm. It was a set of general commands -- the Thou
Shalts and Shalt nots. But then the Word
becomes Flesh in the person of Jesus, the Perfect Man, free of Original Sin,
and thenceforth rather than obey the Law His followers are called upon to
imitate Him, to take Him as the paradigm of the Good Man, whom we must make
ourselves as much like as possible.
Hence the medieval practice of the imitatio
cristi, the Imitation of Christ. or, in its modern vulgar trivialization,
the bumper sticker WWJD -- "What Would Jesus Do?"
According to Kuhn,
ordinary workaday scientists learn how to do science by studying and
reproducing in their laboratories or studies paradigmatic experiments or
observations that are taken as the quintessential examples of what it is to do
science. When they craft their own
experiments or observations, they consciously or unconsciously imitate these
classic examples and thus do science as they have been taught to do it. But when some transformational figure --
Galileo or Kepler or Newton or Faraday or Watson -- does a totally new
experiment or devises a totally new sort of observation that yields surprising,
powerful, transformational results, it captivates bright young scientists
everywhere who begin to imitate it and stop reproducing the old style of work.
Now, if Kuhn's story about the history of science was
correct, and it certainly seemed to be, it had an extraordinary implication
that totally upended the standard account of the development of science. For Kuhn was saying that in each of these
scientific revolutions, an entire body of existing observations was cast aside,
not as incorrect, but as no longer relevant to science at all. Once the new paradigm of scientific research
replaced the old paradigm, these observations simply dropped out of the base of
observations on which scientific theories were erected.
For example, for more than two thousand years, following
Aristotle, scientists had been working with such observational categories as
"hot" and "cold," "wet" and "dry." The theory of the elements was couched in
these categories -- fire is hot and dry, air is hot and wet, earth is cold and dry,
water is cold and wet. The same system
of categories was used to describe the "humours" of the body [phlegm,
bile, choler, etc.] and medicine set as its task restoring the proper balance
of these humours. With the seventeenth
century mathematicization of Physics, observations of hotness, coldness,
wetness, and dryness simply ceased to be considered scientific observations at
all.
But the implication
of this was that there was no gradually expanding body of observations on which
a succession of theories could be tested, and that in turn meant that there was
no ground for claiming that scientific knowledge was expanding, as opposed
simply to changing.
It certainly looked as though modern science was in some
sense better than old-fashioned science, but the clear, simple demonstration of
that intuition evaporated with Kuhn's account of the evolution of science as a
series of paradigm shifts.
Not long after Kuhn shook up our understanding of science,
students of the practice of science noted two other profoundly important ways in
which actual science differs from the story told by philosophers of
science. First of all, modern science is
done by groups of researchers working together in laboratories under the
tutelage or leadership of a senior researcher.
Humanists may work alone as they have for two thousand five hundred
years, but not scientists. This simple
fact immediately raised questions about the social organization of science, and
sociologists began to examine the social structure of scientific activity in
the same way that they were accustomed to examining the social structure of the
corporation or the government or the army.
Second, the size and scope of the scientific enterprise
exploded, with hundreds of thousand, if not millions, of scientists worldwide doing
research and producing reports of their work.
This had a rather unexpected consequence. Since it had become impossible for anyone to
monitor and be aware of all the
scientific research being done even in a single branch of science, not every
experiment, no matter how properly conducted, was noticed and taken up into the
general understanding of the field in which it was carried out. Students of science as a social enterprise
discovered that some experimental reports got noticed, footnoted in the work of
other researchers, referenced by yet other researchers, and in that way became, in effect, scientific facts,
while other experimental reports, not significantly different in the rigor with
which the work had been done or the precision with which that work had been
reported, failed to gain notice and simply dropped out of the body of
experimental facts on which theories were being erected.
In short, what
counted as a scientific fact was, or so it seemed, socially determined, which
was to say, SCIENTIFIC FACTS ARE SOCIAL CONSTRUCTIONS.
So there we are with Social
Text, Alan Sokal, and Stanley Fish.
Well, all of this pretty much flashed through my mind during
the first few minutes of my walk, at which point, more or less when I saw the
second Blue Heron, I had to ask myself what I thought about the Sokal hoax and Stanley
Fish's attempt to defend the editors for their exhibition of scientific
ignorance.
I remained convinced that the editors are horses' asses, not
because they think scientific truth is, in some sense, a social construction,
but because, if I may allude to Fish's baseball analogy, they are like someone
who says, "The thing I really like about baseball is the halftime
show." baseball is a game. Hence it is, in some pretty simple sense, a
social construction. But anyone who
thinks baseball has a halftime show is an idiot, and so is someone who reads
the title of Sokal's send-up and thinks it could be a serious, publishable
piece of work.
I am the one who mistakenly claimed that Fish was Editor of Social Text at the time of the Sokal affaire, while in reality he was only in charge of Duke Univ. Press and later published a passionate defense of the editorial decision.
ReplyDeleteHaving now been shown the error of my ways I proceed to vover my head with ashes in a proper auto-da-fé.
If you have a little bit of ash left over, pass it to me so that I can atone for not recognizing the name of a Nobel Laueate in literature.
ReplyDeleteProf. Wolff,
ReplyDeleteI've never seen that subject expounded in such brief and clear manner. Frankly, even I understood everything. Many thanks.
May God (or genes) give you many more long walks.
Perhaps worth noting, as Kant does in the B edition Preface to the 1st Critique, is the emergence of the experimental method in empirical science. An experiment involves more that mere observation, even via the instruments of enhancement--it involves "cooking the books", as Whitehead reportedly put it, in which what is observed has already been modified by human intervention. That intervention renders the observation of 'nature in itself' impossible, and is one channel of the introduction of ideology into the process.
ReplyDelete