As Marx had the wit to recognize, capitalism, at its core,
is defined and constituted by three interconnected structural
characteristics: First, private ownership
of the means of production; Second, wage labor; and third, the production of
commodities for the purpose of making a profit rather than the production of
goods and services for the purpose of satisfying human needs and desires. [As I write this, I realize that fully to
explain what I have in mind would take several books. But, as it happens, I have written those
books. They are called Understanding Marx and Moneybags Must Be So Lucky. So I am going to have to skim the surface here
and invite you to read the books if you want a fuller exposition and explanation. You can also read From Each According To His Ability, Volume Two of my collected
published and unpublished papers, available as an e-book on Amazon.com. Well, so much for what Tom and Ray Magliozzi
would call the Shameless Commerce Division of The Philosopher's Stone.]
The key to the development of capitalism, and the secret of its
extraordinary profitability, is the historical process by which yeoman farmers
and independent craftspeople were separated from and deprived of access to the
means of production -- land, mines, forests, lakes and oceans, and also the
technology of production -- and were compelled in order to live to become, in
the evocative usage of the early capitalist period, servants of those with control over those means of production, to
become, as we would say today, wage laborers.
It is this historically determined expropriation of the laboring many
that makes it possible for the owners of the means of production to exploit
them, which is to say, to make a profit.
"Free" markets play a central role in this process
of expropriation and exploitation. The
lifting of all restraints on who can take a job creates the possibility of a
permanent surplus of workers looking for jobs -- a reserve army of the
unemployed, as Marx called them in a brilliant phrase. The lifting of restraints on who may produce
goods and on where and to whom and for what price they may be sold clears the
way for cutthroat competition among capitalists [as those who own and control
the means of production are called]. The
result is a constant reinvestment of the profits in the expansion of the scope
of production, resulting in an explosion of output and ever greater profits.
In the early stages of capitalism, there was a great deal of
thoughtful planning, if one can call it that, by individual entrepreneurs [or undertakers, to translate the French
term literally and with delicious irony].
But the desperation of the competition placed great obstacles in the way
of any sort of wider planning within an industry or between industries. There was of course widespread collusion or
collaboration in restraint of trade, but extensive rational planning was
impossible -- not because it violated
the ideology of free trade, but because the organizational, informational, and
structural arrangements needed for such planning had not yet developed.
It is at this point that Marx's true brilliance shows
forth. Marx understood that socialism --
which is to say, collective ownership of the means of production and production
for the satisfaction of human needs rather than for profit -- could not be mandated
by the state, or indeed by any other institutional force, in the absence of those
required arrangements. As he put it in
his Introduction to the Critique of
Political Economy, a new economic order must "grow in the womb of the
old." He had in mind the slow,
centuries-long development of the pre-conditions for capitalism within the
feudal economic order of late medieval Europe, but his insight has wider
application. Until the conditions for
the transition to socialism have developed within capitalism, any attempt to
impose socialism politically or by force is doomed to failure, as the fates of
Russia and China demonstrate.
What are those pre-conditions, and are they in fact now
developing within capitalism? That is the
subject of my essay, "The Future of Socialism," archived on box.net, and
I urge anyone who really wants an answer to those questions to read that essay. The brief answer is that the conditions are
indeed developing within capitalism, prompted not by the brainwashing of
corporate executives by left-wing professors at effete Eastern universities but
by the internal imperatives of the management of capitalist enterprises.
NONE
OF THIS HAS ANYTHING AT ALL TO DO WITH THE ELIMINATION OF MARKETS. If you need a metaphor to grasp this truth,
think of a socialist economy as a vast rainforest with huge trees soaring above
the landscape [the state owned major concentrations of the means of production]
and a rich flora of flowers, shrubs, bushes, and weeds below the canopy [the
sector of small privately owned and run businesses that form, flourish, or fail
just as they do now].
Once it becomes structurally possible to engage in rational planning about the allocation of the
major capital accumulations of the society -- a point that we are fast
approaching -- and also becomes necessary
for some sort of planned allocation to take place, guided by decisions that are
structurally political even if they are now taken by private persons for
private gain -- a situation that is already upon us [this is the central point
of my essay, referenced above] -- then and only then can we talk about
socialism as more than a dream. The
argument against the institution of socialism is not the virtues and joys of
free markets, but the impossibility of socialism before "the new order has
grown in the womb of the old."
But, the "masters of the universe" protest, sitting
astride the great accumulations of capital that generate an endless stream of
profits, have the rich of this world not earned their wealth by their
entrepreneurial skill and daring? This
blog post is too short to deal with that bit of self-congratulatory nonsense as
it deserves. Robert Nozick, in what may
well be the stupidest argument ever advanced by a brilliant and thoroughly
likeable chap, spends three pages in his engaging folie de jeunesse, Anarchy,
State, and Utopia, conjuring a Wilt Chamberlain fantasy that supposedly
justifies the inequality in the distribution of income in a capitalist economy
[see pages 161-163].
So, in answer to Scott [that is where this all started, you
will recall], No, I am not advocating market abolitionism. I am yearning for socialism, which has
nothing to do with the abolition of markets and everything to do with
collective control of the means of production.
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Lad5bc6Gpb4
ReplyDeleteI told you Marx was a brilliant theoretician!
ReplyDeleteRe your Credo: I recently noticed for the first time Socrates reporting, in the Republic (338b):
ReplyDelete“When you say I learn from others,” I said, “you speak the truth, Thrasymachus; but when you say I do not make full payment in thanks, you lie. For I pay as much as I can. I am only able to praise.” [Bloom translation]
The identification is clear: paying as much as one can, i.e., payment in accordance with one’s ability, is payment in full.
I agree that Nozick's Wilt Chamberlain argument does not succeed but would be interested to hear from on precisely why you think it is so bad.
ReplyDeletemany thanks
chris
Briefly, Nozick's example implies [though he does not actually say it] that capitalism has something to do with individual people being very rich, which is nonsense. The rich are always with us, to paraphrase the Good Book. Capitalism does not develop because individuals one way or another amass large piles of personal wealth, anymore than it emerges from the cheese paring of sober individuals capable of deferral of gratification. It emerges from what Marx calls "primitive accumulation of capital." What is more, none of the great capitalist fortunes, and I do mean none, including those of Bill Gates and Steve Jobs, are the result of lots and lots of people being willing to pay them for some talent or gift they have. If you think otherwise, ask yourself exactly who it is who actually makes the IPhones that I and everyone else buy.
ReplyDeleteI've got nothing against Wilt Chamberlain [or LeBron James] getting rich off his athletic skills, and neither did Marx, so far as I can tell. None of that has anything to do with private ownership of the means of production. Bob Nozick's arguments, by and large, are what the English used to call silly clever. See my article on him, archived, for a fuller discussion of his book.
dear professor wolff
ReplyDeletethe fact of primitive accumulation seems a particularly telling criticism of Nozick style justifications of capitalism because it hoists them on their own petard - what is primitive accumulation but a particularly egregious form of coercive property rights violation i.e. theft. I sometimes wonder whether capitalism could be justified if there had been no primitive accumulation and everyone started out with equal shares of resources. Perhaps the appropriate response is that capitalism could never have come into being in such circumstances. What do you think?