Christopher Walsh posts the following interesting question
in the comments section of this blog:
dear professor wolff
the fact of primitive accumulation seems a particularly telling criticism of Nozick style justifications of capitalism because it hoists them on their own petard - what is primitive accumulation but a particularly egregious form of coercive property rights violation i.e. theft. I sometimes wonder whether capitalism could be justified if there had been no primitive accumulation and everyone started out with equal shares of resources. Perhaps the appropriate response is that capitalism could never have come into being in such circumstances. What do you think?
the fact of primitive accumulation seems a particularly telling criticism of Nozick style justifications of capitalism because it hoists them on their own petard - what is primitive accumulation but a particularly egregious form of coercive property rights violation i.e. theft. I sometimes wonder whether capitalism could be justified if there had been no primitive accumulation and everyone started out with equal shares of resources. Perhaps the appropriate response is that capitalism could never have come into being in such circumstances. What do you think?
It is of course obvious that in some sense everyone did
start with equal shares of resources, if we go back far enough to a time when
there were no property rights at all, no law, no organized society, indeed
perhaps no homo sapiens sapiens, but
just bands of homo neanderthalensis. But let us for a moment engage in the kind of
"thought experiment" that anarcho-capitalists, libertarians, and
other such-like lovers of capitalism so favor, and which is Bob Nozick's stock
in trade. Imagine a society of men and
women in which everyone farms a plot of land or plies a trade, and in which, on
market day, they all gather in the town square to exchange what they have
produced for what they need: potatoes
for shoes, cloth for chickens, hats for strawberries, and so forth. How might capitalism as we know it emerge out
of this idyllic starting point? Well,
one imaginative chap who had read a little Friedrich Hayek or Milton Friedman
on a rainy day, might step forth in the town square and in a loud voice
announce that he is prepared to hire some sturdy lads and lasses to work a good
plot of land he has located. The land
should yield a thousand bushels of wheat a year, he says, and he is prepared to
give the ten farmers he seeks to hire fifty bushels of wheat a piece for their
labor [numbers for illustration only -- I am a philosopher, so I haven't a clue
how much wheat one farmer can grow in a year]. Everyone looks at him as though he had lost
his senses. "Why on earth should we
give you half of the crop we raise with the sweat of our brows and the pain of
our backs?" they want to know.
"Well" he says, I had the idea first, and besides I found the
land, so I have decided to take half the crop for myself." The poor sap gets no takers, and goes back to
the library [they do have libraries] to see whether he can find another book
that will give him the clue to becoming a capitalist.
First he tries some old Puritans, who preach the virtues of
discipline, self-sacrifice, and the deferral of gratification. Apparently the secret to becoming a
capitalist is to live a life of self-denial and carefully put to one side a
part of every year's crop, or a portion of every year's pile of shoes --
whatever happens to be one's way of making a living. So he tries this, and sure enough it seems to
work. After a year of hard farming
labor, he sets aside ten of the one hundred bushels of wheat he has grown, which
he exchanges for some additional tools and better seed. Year after year, he keeps at it, and he does
indeed prosper, so much so that he is visibly better off than those of his fellows
who are less able or willing to engage in disciplined self-denial. But he still does not have anyone working for
him, because whenever he tries to hire some chaps to farm his land, he finds
that he must either offer them the full product of their labor, which doesn't
do him any good whatsoever, or he must offer them less than the product of
their labor, in which case they laugh at him and go back to their own land.
Well, twenty years go by, and our aspiring capitalist is
getting on in life, so he decides to go back to the library for one last search
of the available books. There he
stumbles on a copy of Capital, and
after he has plowed through the mysterious and quite unhelpful discussions of
the fetishism of commodities and the working day [what, he wonders, are factories],
he comes upon Part VIII "The So-Called Primitive Accumulation." The heavens open, the angels sing, and he
realizes that he has found the Promised Land.
Off he goes back to his village, where he proceeds to use the little bit
extra he has saved by his rigorous self-denial to hire a few bully boys who
prefer beating up farmers to working the land.
They pretty quickly drive the hard-working farmers from the good land,
and stand ready to guard it for its new owner, our capitalist hero. Now, when he goes to the square and offers to
pay fifty bushels of wheat for enough work to produce one hundred bushels of
wheat, the dispossessed farmers, driven from their land, have no choice but to
accept his offer. Agricultural
capitalism has arrived. Can financial
capitalism be far behind?
Modern-day apologists for capitalism simply assume without
explanation that a few people will own the means of production -- the state
standing behind them to protect that ownership with the full force of law and
police -- while the many have nothing but their labor and are therefore forced
to sell that labor to the owners of the means of production for a wage. These apologists focus all their attention on
the wage bargain struck in the labor market, worrying endlessly about whether
it is a bargain "freely arrived at," without ever really asking
themselves how the participants in the wage bargain came to be in the situation
that defines their relative bargaining power.
To answer Christopher Walsh's question simply, capitalism never develops out of a situation in
which everyone has an equal share of the resources, unless first a process of
expropriation and primitive accumulation has taken place.
I have always avoided arguing from thought experiments because it's difficult to avoid simplification-to-null (ie, does the setup refer to a complete and concrete situation aka resemble reality, and how much?) So I'm inclined to ask what's missing in the exercise. Almost any writer is cannon fodder for this type of objection, partly because the experiment is usually conceived in an ideal framework, purged of impurities, so to speak, and if one can find discrepancies from "the real world," then the experiment is already running on only one leg. But I digress.
ReplyDeleteIn your allegory above, I wonder how it would change the discussion to point out that Mr Capitalist Wannabe could have found a different strategy, which seems to me more like the actual history we're after (though I'm almost sure you'll disagree). And that strategy is to pay some of his fellow farmers for their land first, and then for their labor, in exchange not only for a (diminished) share of the product, but also to relieve them of risk in case of failure (drought, for instance). In other words, what seems to be missing in the tale is how Mr Cap assumes control of the means of production (besides the labor). And if this is accounted for, then the free transfer of both land/means and risk to Mr Cap establishes some dominion over the product, does it not?
(Free transfer in the sense of "freely agreed" not free of charge. LOL)
ReplyDeleteDoesn't this just assume that there are no economies of scale or returns to specialization?
ReplyDelete'The land should yield a thousand bushels of wheat a year, he says, and he is prepared to give the ten farmers he seeks to hire fifty bushels of wheat a piece for their labor... Everyone looks at him as though he had lost his senses. "Why on earth should we give you half of the crop we raise with the sweat of our brows and the pain of our backs?" '
If the answer is "because by the sweat of your brow and the pain of your back each of you will only generate twenty-five bushels," it is not clear to me that they will laugh.
If ten working together and dividing their labor are four times as productive as ten working individually, each trying to do everything, then there is room for organizational innovation. This might take the form of the ten pooling their efforts in an egalitarian co-op-- but organization is its own difficult and complicated work, and the moreso as the numbers increase. So that gives the would-be capitalist something with which to bid: "OK, 75% of the product, plus I do all the organizational work." Or if, as in your example, the would-be capitalist has some accumulated surplus to spend: "75% of the *expected value* of the product, with you insured against the year-to-year fluctuations. Or 60% of the expected value, plus 40% of the surplus if we exceed expectations."
The division of labor, organizational innovation, and insurance functions can do a lot of work (in practice and in theory). Maybe they can't do enough; maybe the co-op will always be able to outbid the capitalist. But nothing in he present parable shows that. Wage labor purports to offer an *increase* in *absolute* compensation, at the price of the *decrease* you note in the share of product retained. Is it a necessary truth that that's a laughable offer?
You are quite right that there is a great deal more to be said, but remember that I was answering a question about how capitalism gets started, and I do not think any of these kinds of considerations explain the vast and rapid accumulation of capital and concommitant separation of the workers from ownership of the means of production that are involved.
ReplyDeleteWe actually have a good test case in America. At the end of the Civil War, the planters were desperate to retain the labor of their former slaves, since without it their land was worthless. But it turned out that the freedmen and freedwomen did not want to work on the admittedly more efficient plantations even as wage laborers. Hence the Black Codes and convict labor that forced them back onto the plantations.
What made the plantations so efficient was a kind of organized gang labor overseen by "slave drivers" and the freedpeople wanted none of it.
These "Robinsonades" as Marx called them [after Robinson crusoe] are ideological rationalizations of capitalism, not serious explanations of its emergence out of feudalism.
Well, I'm of the view that that emergence was many phenomena and not one. But for now I think the point is that the counter-Robinsonade is also not a serious explanation. Thought experiments and simplifications and hypotheticals have their uses if one is *very* careful with them, but if the point of this was to show the impossibility of capitalism without primitive accumulation, I don't think it succeeds.
ReplyDeleteI'm not sure how to take the term "impossible." Logically impossible? Of course not. Impossible even to imagine? Of course not, one can imagine anything that is consistent. Possible in the familasir historical sense? I would say capitalism is impossible without capital accumulation. Is that proved by a little story? Of course not. I was responding to a uestion about Nozick. But realistically, historically, how would you expect the vast majority of a population to be permanently separated from their historical ownership or access to the means of production and hence be forced to work for wages?
ReplyDelete