I have almost completely failed to persuade the commentators
on this blog to break loose from the traditions of Marxist jargon and
hagiography so that they can think in fresh ways about our current social,
economic, and political situation [I except Wallace Stevens, whose comments
have been very much in the spirit I was trying to engender.] I have tried personal stories, reminiscences,
and bits and snatches of statistical data culled from the Internet, all without
much success. I am going to have one
more go at it, and then, as they say in the soaps, move on. I will be talking about Plato, Marx, and Max
Weber, so maybe the manifest seriousness of such a discourse will encourage
folks to pay close attention.
Let me set the stage for my remarks today by quoting part of
Stevens’ useful discussion of the work of Gerald Cohen. Here is Stevens:
“Cohen mounts a very strong critique of what he calls the
“obstetric doctrine,” or “radical endogeny” in classical Marxism—i.e., “that
the full development of a problem always issues in its solution.” In Cohen’s
view, this doctrine, inherited from Hegel, leads, when applied to historical
and social issues, to the belief that a solution arises when “the problem
itself is consummated, when it reaches its highest pitch.” Cohen: “Consider,
for example, the problem posed by capitalism, as Marx and Engels envisaged
it—the problem, to describe it simply, of massive power to produce, alongside
massive poverty. As that problem deepens, its solution looms, as and because
the problem deepens.” Cohen cites the famous passage in the “Contribution to
the Critique of Political Economy,” (“No social order ever perishes before…”)
and concludes that this leads, for Marxism, to the “happy result” that “Social
repair—like conceptual repair, as Hegel conceived it—cannot come from without
and always will be found within, provided that the thing is really broken. The
utopian project is, therefore, both impossible and unnecessary.””
Inasmuch as I have several times quoted favorably that
famous passage from the Contribution to the
Critique of Political Economy, and have made it the central insight of my
paper, “The Future of Socialism,” the best way I can see to make clear what I
have been trying to say is to explain why, in my acceptation of that passage, I
do not fall into the error of drawing from the “obstetric doctrine” the
conclusion of “radical endogeny.” [I
have my problems with some of Cohen’s work, but you have to love the wit of
these two phrases.] Here is the original
passage [in an English translation, of course]:
No social order disappears before all
of the productive forces for which there is room in it have been developed, and
new, higher relations of production never appear before the material components
of their existence have matured in the womb of the old society.
[Just to make the obvious explicit,
Cohen gets the phrase “the obstetric doctrine” from Marx’s image of the new
order maturing in the womb of the old, which might seem to imply that social
change is a job for an obstetrician rather than a surgeon or a butcher.]
There are three very different ways in
which social theorists have understood and employed such terms as democracy, aristocracy, dictatorship, feudalism, capitalism, socialism,
bureaucracy, working class, and
bourgeoisie. The oldest, which we
may attribute in one form or another to Plato and also to Aristotle, is to
construe such terms as the names of pure forms or Ideas, which find approximate
instantiation in the experienced world. It
follows that when we seek to employ these terms, we must first analyze them as
pure forms in order to understand their true nature. Then we can look at the world and determine, with
regard to some actual society, whether it does or does not have a feudal
economy or a capitalist economy, whether it is a democracy or an aristocracy,
and so forth.
The second way in which we can
understand these terms is to construe them as summary descriptions of a variety
of complex and multifarious social realities.
What is a democracy? Do a
comparative description and analysis of several dozen nation states that
identify themselves as democracies and look for their common characteristics. What is the role of governmental regulation
of economic activity in a capitalist economy?
Once again, examine a spectrum of national economies that self-identify
as capitalist, and see what sorts of actions the central governments take to
regulate the activity of corporations, hedge funds, or venture capital firms.
The third way to understand such terms –
the correct way, in my judgment – is to construe them as what Max Weber called “ideal
types.” There is a rather chewy Wikipedia entry on “ideal
types” that captures Weber’s central notion, albeit not too felicitously. Here is the first paragraph:
“An ideal type is formed from characteristics and elements
of the given phenomena, but it is not meant to correspond to all of the
characteristics of any one particular case. It
is not meant to refer to perfect things, moral ideals nor to statistical averages but rather to stress
certain elements common to most cases of the given phenomena. It is also
important to pay attention that in using the word “ideal” Max Weber refers to
the world of ideas (German: Gedankenbilder "thoughtful pictures") and not to perfection;
these “ideal types” are idea-constructs that help put the seeming chaos of
social reality in order.”
The ideal type is a hypothetical construction designed to help us in
thinking about social realities so complex that they threaten to evade
understanding. The test of the adequacy
of an ideal type is its success in leading us to new, suggestive understandings
that can be confirmed by detailed empirical data. If an ideal type ceases to yield useful
results, it should be revised in the light of new data.
This, to put it simply, is how I understand Marx’s famous statement about the
material components of new, higher relations of production maturing in the womb
of the old society. First of all, Marx’s
conception of capitalism [and also of feudalism] is in Weber’s sense of the
term an ideal type. Marx looks at the
world around him, in all its endless complexity, and he identifies certain
elements that he judges are somehow centrally important in capitalism. He ignores the forms of dress or speech or
the religious preferences of the “new men” whom everyone is fascinated with –
the entrepreneurs starting businesses and becoming very rich in one generation –
and he concludes that what is really important about them, what is definitive,
is that they hire wage labor and produce goods for sale in markets, all the
while guided by a fierce concentration on the profit they are making. Marx looks backward in time to the centuries
prior to his own, and finds that certain defining marks of these capitalists
make an appearance of sorts very much earlier in time, when the dominant social
and economic order is feudal in nature.
The more Marx learns about the centuries leading up to the nineteenth,
the more it becomes clear to him that these early evidences of the development of
new forms of economic activity and new ways of thinking about economic activity
are essential precursors of the capitalism that has come to maturity in England
and is just beginning to develop in his native Prussia. Marx comes to realize that the dramatic
political revolutions that dominate everyone’s thinking – the French Revolution,
the English Revolution, the American Revolution – are not the initiations of
new economic arrangements but are actually the ratifications in the political
realm of economic changes that are well under way.
All of this, worked up into a theory vastly more complex than I have
indicated, leads him to conclude that the large scale transition from one form
of economic organization to another requires that many of the elements of the
new economic organization have their roots in changes that have taken place
within the old economic organization – that the “the
material components of their existence have matured in the womb of the old
society,” in Marx’s pregnant phrase.
Guided by Marx, who is, in this as in
so much else, wise and insightful and profound, I ask myself: What are the developments now taking place
within advanced capitalism that could be understood as the elements of what
might become a transition to socialism?
In my essay, “The Future of Socialism,” I focus on one important
development within large corporations.
In a blog post I put up a little while back, I focus on other
developments. I do not draw from Marx’s
text the absurd conclusion that socialism will arrive by itself, as it were, if
we just sit back and wait for it to mature in the womb of capitalism. But I also do not make the mistake of
supposing that a transition to socialism just requires enough brave, dedicated
fighters at the barricades, regardless of the stage of development of the
capitalism they are trying to overthrow.
Therefore, I spend my time looking at
capitalism and trying to discern in its evolution elements that could play a
part of a transition to socialism. I do
not make the mistake of supposing that faithfulness to the ipsissima verba of Marx’s writings is an important part of any such
transition, nor do I imagine that Marx already knew and said pretty much all I
need to know about the world today.
OK.
That is as clear as I can make it.
"I have almost completely failed to persuade the commentators on this blog to break loose from the traditions of Marxist jargon and hagiography so that they can think in fresh ways about our current social, economic, and political situation"
ReplyDeleteSpeaking strictly for myself, I usually speak in Marxist jargon when I'm around Marxists, and I avoid it when I'm not. I'm not quite sure why it's problematic to use Marxist jargon on a blog whose author identifies as a Marxist. Words like exploitation, alienation, fetish, and species-being, can all be translated into more colloquial terms, but then the sentences and explanations which employ them would have to be longer.
While I find the discussion rewarding, my frustration is two fold. On the one hand, sometimes it feels like we are in the church of Marx where the point of the discussion is to advance the correct interpretation of a particular gospel.
ReplyDeleteThe other frustration is that we have not discussed values: what values incubating in the womb of capitalism might support
the transition to a kind of socialism and then be further nurtured? I think the steady expansion of the franchise, the embrace of gender equality and sexual identity equality, an embrace/protection of the commons and respect for nature, a full articulation of "black lives matter," the rejection of obscene inequality, solidarity with victims of imperialism, the value-assemblage of beauty (yes, to be explicated), pleasure in work, expressivism are values that seem to steadily percolate to the surface and then collide with institutions that foster the equation of freedom with property rights and success with accumulation.
What annoys me about these kind of discussions is that it feels like we are playing chess or having a graduate seminar among a bunch of white guys (just guessing) who's work is not alienating are who are somewhat financially secure. I'm curious what the others would point to in their daily lives as things/activities from which they need liberation. Constant networking? the organization of life around investment opportunities? the anxiety of financial insecurity? segregation? what good stuff would I and others get more of under socialism, and what bad stuff would be eliminated or fade away? Marx is great. Marxology boring.
This seems oddly relevant: The most powerful progressive force in the 1st world today seems to be the Pope. (nb: 'most' modifies 'powerful' not 'progressive'.
ReplyDelete"break loose from the traditions of Marxist jargon and hagiography so that they can think in fresh ways about our current social, economic, and political situation"
ReplyDeleteAnd the magic answer became (with all due respect) a regurgitation of the Marxist formulation with a Weberian twist. Reminds me of a line from Hegel's Phenomenology ('even as there is an empty breadth, there is an empty depth, an intensity void of content).
[As an aside, it should be noted that Weber's method involved breaking down an extremely complex phenomenon into its components and then choosing each one in sequence as a constant, tracing its effect on the other variables. Weber also offers no method for determining the interrelation of factors, the amount of influence pertaining to each one or their temporal variations. In this sense, the ideal type method prevents the possibility of establishing time sequences. Of course, in his defense, this may have more to do with the fact that Weber, unlike Marx, felt one could only grasp segments of social reality but never its totality. Whereas Marx, in the course of his presentation, shows how individual categories are unfolded from one another (how one category necessitates the existence of another) and does not simply present categories in succession or alongside each other. Moreover, Weber's view of theory as only ideal typical as well as his employment of the ideal type method has the tendency to lead to different distortions, for example in his overemphasis of the concepts of vocation and predestination. His approach is suffused by a tendency towards idealisation, while comparatively neglecting secular factors, economic, political and technological. More on Weber -- there was nothing original about his work on the conditions permitting the rise of capitalism. It stemmed directly from Marx and was shared by many scholars in Germany at the time. Marxists as well as the economists of the Historical School discussed it at great length. The originality of Weber's approach, however, consisted in something rather simple. While other scholars studied the economic causes of the rise of capitalism by looking at the process of its industrial growth in Western Europe, Weber on the other hand, concentrated on cases where capitalism failed to develop. That is why many scholars have used Weber's argument in the PE as a way to understand why some non-Western countries have achieved modernisation while others have not) .
To repeat some earlier points:
The concept 'utopian socialism' was introduced and discussed in the CM by Marx and Engels as a way to describe socialist and quasi socialist intellectuals who designed imaginary blueprints or visions of a socialist future. The communists, on the other hand, including Marx and Engels, never speculated on the detailed organisation of a future socialist or communist society; concerning themselves with the sole objective of building a workers' movement strong enough to overthrow capitalism. It is not so much a matter of quoting saint Marx -- generations of communists and anarchists, especially since the formation and collapse of the IWMA, have debated these issues and have taken clear stances on them. Have you? Given that you self identify as Marxist and Anarchist.
As Engels (and Marx following him) understood, "the condition of the working class is the starting point of all social movements today." So a discussion of socialism is not possible without looking at working class conditions and demands and their significance for the general class struggle to overthrow capitalism.
Now despite the fact that Marx consciously took up the position not to speculate on the detailed organisation of a future socialist society (for good reasons) where he does write a little bit about socialism or freely associated labour, he (correctly) focuses on one thing: labour time.
"In fact, the realm of freedom actually begins only where labour which is determined by necessity and mundane considerations ceases; thus in the very nature of things it lies beyond the sphere of actual material production. Just as the savage must wrestle with Nature to satisfy his wants, to maintain and reproduce life, so must civilised man, and he must do so in all social formations and under all possible modes of production. With his development this realm of physical necessity expands as a result of his wants; but, at the same time, the forces of production which satisfy these wants also increase. Freedom in this field can only consist in socialised man, the associated producers, rationally regulating their interchange with Nature, bringing it under their common control, instead of being ruled by it as by the blind forces of Nature; and achieving this with the least expenditure of energy and under conditions most favourable to, and worthy of, their human nature. But it nonetheless still remains a realm of necessity. Beyond it begins that development of human energy which is an end in itself, the true realm of freedom, which, however, can blossom forth only with this realm of necessity as its basis. The shortening of the working-day is its basic prerequisite."
ReplyDeleteThe passage ends: 'The shortening of the working-day is its basic prerequisite.' By which we assume that Marx means the shortening of the working day is the first step towards time for oneself, free of the necessity of producing for material needs.
And there is that foot note cited at the very end of Chapter 10, quoting a Factory Inspector as saying: “A still greater boon is the distinction at last made clear between the worker’s own time and his master’s. The worker knows now when that which he sells is ended, and when his own begins; and by possessing a sure foreknowledge of this, is enabled to prearrange his own minutes for his own purposes.” (l.c., p. 52.) [the words in italics are mine because they are also the last carefully chosen words Marx picked out to end the famous chapter on the Working Day. Marx intentionally focuses on the length of the working day (labour time) as opposed to say wages, working conditions, etc, in chapter 10 for a very good reason which I leave to the reader to figure out why]
and then there is this footnote as well:
“By making them masters of their own time (the Factory Acts) have given them a moral energy which is directing them to the eventual possession of political power” (l.c., p. 47).
I personally find this much more profound and useful.