The comments attendant upon my remarks about Rawls’ work
incline me to say something of a systematic nature about how I read a work of
philosophy. The first major works with
which I engaged seriously were Hume’s Treatise
and Kant’s First Critique, which
together were the subject of my doctoral dissertation. Both works are long, extremely complex, and
filled with seemingly endless detail, all of which is, as one might expect,
elegantly and intelligently presented.
But despite the fact that I became deeply steeped in both works and knew
that detail intimately, when it came time for me to write about them, I ignored
the detail, the elaborations and fine work, as it were, and instead approached both
works in a quite different fashion. I
saw Hume and Kant, and then by extension other great philosophers as well, as
engaged in trying to bring to the surface and articulate deep conceptual
insights into complex core arguments. My
job as a commentator, I decided, was to try to dive as deeply as they had, to follow
them like Gandalf wrestling with the Borlag in the caves of Moria, and to grasp
those central ideas, shaking them loose from the accompanying detailed elaborations
as though they were barnacles growing on the hull of a sunken ship. Very early in my philosophical work, I realized
that I experience philosophical arguments as stories, which it is my job to
re-tell as simply and clearly as I can.
The greatest philosophers, I found, sometimes could see more
deeply into certain ideas than they could say clearly the core of those
ideas. So it was that in my struggle with
the Treatise, I concluded that to
understand Hume’s most powerful arguments, it was necessary to set aside his
claim that every idea is a copy of a preceding impression, and instead bring to
the surface the fact that at the critical turning points in his arguments, he
appealed not to ideas copied from impressions but to acts of the mind. Hence my phrase “theory of mental activity”
which I used both to describe Hume’s argument and as part of the title of my
book on the Critique.
Kant posed a problem of the highest order. On the one hand, Kant presented a theory of
almost unmanageable detail and complexity, in which the detailed elaboration
was said by him to be central to his argument.
On the other hand, as I plunged deeper and deeper into the central
portions of the Critique, it seemed
clear to me that one could only articulate Kant’s enormously powerful argument
by simply ignoring almost all of that fretwork and taking seriously in my
reading of him certain passages that he himself said were unimportant or needed
even to be omitted from the Second Edition.
Is this the right
way to read a great work of philosophy?
Of course not. Countless
commentators on a great text have grappled successfully and valuably with
portions of that text that I have chosen simply to ignore. Is it a
right way to read a great work of philosophy.
I believe that it is, but there is no point in arguing that as a general
proposition. In each individual case,
readers must judge for themselves whether my monomaniacally focused reading of
the text is valuable to them. If it is,
then in that case I have been successful.
It is in this way that I approached A Theory of Justice. The
fretwork and elaboration interested me not at all, but I saw in the book a
central argument worth extracting from the text and engaging with. Those who do not find this approach illuminating
ought simply to move on. For those whose
minds work as mine does, my analysis may be enlightening.
7 comments:
Would the word 'agon' as applied to poets by Bloom apply to your dealings with Hume and Kant?
It would if I were as great a philosopher as they, which I am not. But it most certainly applies to Hegel's relationhip to kant, or Marx's relationship to Hegel.
So
Wolff is to Kant as Bloom is to Shakespeare?
I don't know philosophers nearly as well as I know Tolkien. Gandalf fought a Balrog in Moria, and both were killed in that battle- so be careful in your fights. On the bright side, Gandalf was sent back to finish his mission in Middle Earth, and the Balrog was just dead. Of course, comparing yourself to Gandalf- one of the wisest and most powerful entities on the side of the Good in Middle Earth- might be further evidence of that arrogance thing you had been talking about :)
Bernard Gert included a critique of Rawls's veil of ignorance in Morality: Its Nature and Justification. I'll include a link -- I don't have time at the moment to copy out and comment on the relevant excerpt (last paragraph). But I thought it might be useful to draw attention to it.
I do have time for a capsule summary of Gert's point: going under Rawls's veil of ignorance will guarantee unanimity, but this is unnecessarily restrictive: morality (and justice) require only impartiality. Gert also claims that Rawls requires unanimity because of Rawls's notion of rationality requires it; Gert provides a different account of rationality.
Best Qualified Leads For MCA method has several leading elements needed to modify the MCA Leads Guide to the approaching jobs in the Qualified MCA Leads Data.
Post a Comment