A word of explanation is called for. Thirty-five years ago I was asked to prepare a paper on Kant's legal philosophy that was originally intended to be published in the Columbia Law Journal as part of the proceedings of a conference, but the students in charge of the journal wisely recognized that what I have written did not really call for such distinguished recognition so instead they asked me to write a report of the conference. This paper is that report. When the students read it, they were obviously appalled and I got a collective phone call from the editors of the Journal in which they delicately suggested some editing changes. I said that as a matter of principle I never allowed anybody to edit what I write but that I would not be at all upset if they chose simply not to publish it. There was an explosive outpouring of breath that had been held tight by students who saw their careers going down the tubes and we parted friends. I put the paper back in my file drawer and, as they say in the soaps, moved on.
WHY
INDEED
by
Johannes Climacus
Responsible for publication
Robert Paul Wolff
The Workshop in Kantian Legal
Theory, of which the papers reproduced here are a partial record, was a curious
event, withal. Nineteen men and one woman, closeted - and cossetted - for three
days in Columbia University's Arden House for the avowed purpose of discussing
the jurisprudential theories of the greatest philosopher who ever lived,
Immanuel Kant. Fifteen hundred dollars plus expenses for the six authors of the papers circulated in advance for discussion, five hundred for those charged
with participating in the discussion, the bill to be paid by the right-wing
Liberty Fund, whose minatory representative, eerily resembling the Jehovah's
Witnesses who every day radiate from their home in Brooklyn Heights to proselytize
the faith, attended each session to make sure that the hired hands put in a
full day's work.
Five of the nineteen were
professional philosophers, four of them Kant scholars who had made their
reputations struggling with one or another of Kant's great works. Twelve hours
of concentrated discussion on Kant's philosophy was, in Eliza
Doolittle's words, mother's milk to them, and Philosophy being what it is, the
pay wasn't bad either. But the remaining fourteen were professors of law - two
from Canada, one from England, a lone representative of the German Federal
Republic, and the rest from the United States. What, one could not help but
wonder, were they doing there? What could Kant possibly have to say to them
that would justify three days of unrelenting Kantshtick?
Most voluble of the nineteen was
Fletcher's colleague, Bruce Ackerman, brilliant, precocious, enormously — and
on occasion, with some justification — pleased with himself. Antaeus—like,
Ackerman would draw renewed strength from the sound of his own voice, so that
launched upon a comment of finite scope, he would be refreshed by his words,
and extend his remarks to fill all available space and time. Competing with
Ackerman for the floor most often was the radical philosopher and sometime Kant
scholar Robert Paul Wolff, whose face, contorted by a persistant facial tic,
showed excitement, disgust, irritation, and exasperation in quick succession.
Ackerman and Wolff, like the two youngest boys at a Seder, frequently competed
to see who could ask the most questions from a reclining position, both of them
manifestly expecting an indulgent Jewish mother to pat them on the head and offer
them another piece of cake.
Intervening
with impassioned criticisms that often outran their target somewhat was
newly—tenured Andrzej Rapaczynski, also of Columbia Law School. Rapaczynski,
quite possibly the philosophically quickest mind at the conference, had many
years earlier been a brilliant student in the Columbia philosophy department,
and had studied with Wolff. Now that he is safely tenured, it can perhaps be
acknowledged that Rapaczynski is really a philosopher, not a Jurisprude,
and in his youthful enthusiasm he was frequently less successful than his
fellow philosophers in concealing his dismay at the appallingly low level of
understanding of Kant manifested around the table.
Across
from Ackerman and Wolff sat tall, thin Mary Gregor, bent in a question mark of deference to her neighbor, Douglas
Dryer, a long—time Kant scholar from Canada. As the only real expert present on
the subject of the conference — she is the author of the major commentary on
the work under discussion — Gregor was of course almost silent during the three
days. Genuine technical knowledge was in short supply, and would, if too often
displayed, have tended to inhibit the free flow of conversation.
Casting something of a pall on the proceedings was Professor Dr. Wolfgang Naucke of Frankfurt University, a Professor of Law and a Judge. For Naucke, it appeared, Kant constitutes the last barrier separating western civilization from barbarism, although whether from the left or from the right remained for a while unclear. Naucke's discussion of Kant was couched in a grammatical mode that might be dubbed the incantatory imperative, inspiring in the listener contradictory impulses to cheer and salute. Naucke's true colors were revealed almost by accident, midway through the discussion of his paper. Asked directly and flatly whether he considered Kant's jurisprudence incompatible with the welfare state, he replied, laconically, yes. At that, Wolff, who had been dozing, sat bolt upright like the dormouse at the Mad Hatter's tea party and confessed himself suddenly to have recaptured an interest in the proceedings.
In striking contrast to Naucke, Herbert Morris, Dean
of Humanities at UCLA, brought a welcome touch of laid—back California cool to
the conference, taking the sting out of the Morningside Heights intensity of
Ackerman, Rapaczynski, et al. Morris is well known for his philosophical
discussions of the theory of punishment, and had in previous years carried on a
debate in the literature on that subject with one of the Kant scholars present,
Jeffrie Murphy of Arizona State. Prompted by a question during the discussion
of Murphie's paper, Morris treated the conference to an exquisite illustration
of how to expound a systematic philosophical position while appearing merely to
reminisce about an experience on a California freeway. Morris' impromptu
remarks were one of the few moments of genuine style in an otherwise pedestrian
three days.
The
non—Canadian North Americans around the table were intermittently chivvied,
with ironic deprecation, by crypto—Thomist Ernest Weinrib from the University
of Toronto. Weinrib, and his killer rabbit sidekick Peter Benson from McGill,
were the only lawyers at the conference who appeared seriously to be interested
in the substance of the law. Weinrib's complaint, the internal incoherence of
tort law south of his border, and the contrasting beauty and elegance of
Canadian tort law, utterly mystified the philosophers around the table, but
appeared to be an old familiar tune to the other lawyers.
As Spinoza noted, the self comes to know itself only as it sees itself reflected in others. Hence lovers need the beloved, actors crave audiences, and professors tolerate students. Fletcher, understanding these needs, had, like a good host, provided a symbolic student presence in the form of the editorial board of the Columbia Law Journal. They were of course enjoined from interrupting the heavenly discourses by juvenile interventions, but they were permitted to be present at the proceedings, with the understanding that they would in due course turn over the pages of their journal to the finished products.
And there they all
were, removed from the distractions of Manhattan, fed and cared for by a
silent, efficient Arden House staff, serenaded by a chamber trio on the second
evening, and embarked on twelve hours of investigation Of the Rechtslehre,
Part One of Kant's late, minor work, THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS.
Each
two-hour session was devoted to one of the prepared papers, which
all conference participants had received in advance. Robert Paul Wolff led off
on the first afternoon. Wolff, accustomed to the terse prose style of the
philosophical world, and mistakenly expecting to have to read his paper aloud,
had been well along in the drafting of eighteen or twenty carefully crafted
pages when a chance phone call to Fletcher had revealed that the other
participants were producing 'fifty to eighty pages.' Panicked by the potential
mortification of showing up with the shortest paper on the block, Wolff
discarded his draft and began again. Since the paper was intended for non-philosophers, he reasoned, a fair
amount of space could usefully be devoted to teaching them something about
Kant. Having written two books on Kant's philosophy, and having taught Kant for
thirty years, Wolff found it no great strain to churn out fifty pages in the
next four days, and it was this effort that the conferees had all read. [Wolff
was inordinately pleased with his effort, and much excited by the prospect of
publishing a fifty-page paper in the Columbia Law Journal. The students, not
fooled for a moment, spoke many kind words to him but chose not to publish.]
The
gravamen of Wolff's effort was that just as Kant's moral philosophy has to be read in the light of
the deeper doctrines of the CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON, in which context it
becomes clear that there are fundamental contradictions between the two which
mortally undermine the moral philosophy, so too Kant's legal philosophy must be
interpreted through its relation to Kant's fundamental epistemological
teachings, with equally disastrous consequences. The implication of Wolff's
remarks was that the Kantian legal philosophy was without defensible
foundation. Consequently, although the session was pronounced a great success,
and was said to have started the conference off in fine style, Wolff's argument
was henceforth completely ignored.
A
break for drinks and dinner, and the participants returned, fueled and
lubricated, for an evening discussion of Fletcher's 89 page note. Fletcher's
paper bearing only a parametric relation to Kant, there was considerable
hermeneutical space between object—text and subject—discourse within which an
unfettered conversation could develop, and everyone pitched in with enthusiasm.
And so it went for two more days.
The next morning, Naucke's apocalyptic warnings were followed by Weinrib's animadversions,
with Murphy's scholarly and professional addendum to his well—known writings on
Kant's retributive theory of punishment preparing the group for the chamber
music to follow. The conference was brought to a close with an elegantly
evasive defense, by the cultivated Oxford homophobe John Finnis, of his utterly
appalling paper. David Richards, a
principal target of Finnis' crabbed and ungenerous remarks, conducted himself
with a restraint that was made all the more effective by the eloquence of his
reply. The Finnis session was graced by the one moment of genuine scholarship:
in rebuttal of Finnis' implausible attempt to claim Kant's support for his own
sectarian views, Mary Gregor,
And so we return to the question that provoked Wolff
to a restless quizzing of his fellow conferees: why Kant? What were busy,
successful, worldly lawyers [worldly, at the very least, by philosophical
standards] doing locked in three days of debate about Kant? Some of the participants suggested that
they were looking for a shtick to beat the
utilitarianism of the left. Others identified the 'law and economics' of the
right as their target. But neither group gave any indication of a serious
interest in the arguments with which Kant had sought to establish his
arcane and rather paradoxical philosophical theses. Arguments, unlike shticks,
not being adaptable to purposes other than those for which they were fashioned, what did anyone at the conference
hope to get from Kant?
The answer is this: lawyers, unlike serious philosophers [but, in this
regard, quite like second—rate philosophers], do not actually seek to demonstrate
the positions they defend. Rather, they aim to assimilate issues with which
they are concerned to the existing structure of laws and precedents in hopes
that courts will construe those issues in ways that favor their clients. For
this purpose, lawyers need a large and versatile armamentarium of concepts,
categories, distinctions, and argument fragments with the aid of which they can
articulate intuitions, convictions, or interests to which they are already
committed. Both utilitarianism and cost/benefit analysis provide just such
weapons to advocates of the left or the right, none of whom can be said ever to
Prove their positions, but all of whom gain argumentative leverage from
their ability to embed their advocacy in a preexisting proof—structure.
Kant's
philosophy is a rich resource of arguments, concepts, and distinctions,
already elaborated into an architectonic of subordinations and coordinations,
incomparably high in intellectual and academic status, and lying entirely
within the public domain. Philosophically speaking, it is to utilitarianism,
cost/benefit analysis, or Rawls' THEORY OF JUSTICE what a strategic nuclear
weapon is to a medium tank. Invocations of the Categorical imperative or the
noumena/phenomena distinction instantaneously confer on the author vast quantities of what teen-age players of Dungeons and Dragons call 'hit
points.' In the jargon of the old gangster movies, Kant is the Equalizer. Since lawyers are a combative
lot, and good lawyers are winners, three days at Arden House probably seemed like a pretty fair price to
pay for a chance at a
secret weapon.
Did
the Liberty Fund get its money's worth? One hopes not, considering that
organization's political orientation. Perhaps the readers of this journal can
decide for themselves, having read the best of the papers revised and refined in the light of
three days of debate. After the participants had left for their several homes,
the following notes were discovered at the seat that had been occupied by
Robert Paul Wolff. Wolff apparently found the Weinrib paper philosophically
suggestive and worthy of serious consideration. His fragmentary jottings have
been Englished, as editors like to say, and are offered hare for what they
might be worth.
Comments by Robert Paul Wolff on Ernest
Weinrib's Paper
A very interesting
piece of work. W. is clearly a Thomist who sees in K.'s notion of an 'Idea of
Reason' a modern rationale for the Aristotelian-Thomist conception of the telos
or internal purpose of a natural kind. Except that the law, being a human product,
can have no other telos than what its
makers impute to it. W. seems
hesitant to come out from behind Kant's skirts and declare himself. It is
difficult, merely from the text, to tell whether he endorses the notion that
the unity of the law is an idea of Reason, or merely attributes it to Kant. But
the evident passion with which W. advances his views decides clearly for the
former.
W.
is certainly correct in his diagnosis of Fletcher and Calabresi on torts
[whatever they are], but a diagnosis is not yet a condemnation, let alone a
refutation. Why shouldn't those two merely grant W's point, and agree that,
absent a purposeful God who has set for Mankind the task of articulating an
internally coherent Law, our legal institutions quite properly reflect the
fundamental disunity of our society? [Probably Calabresi would be more
comfortable with that response than Fletcher.]
But leaving aside such considerations, which bear
merely on the truth of W's position, there are serious difficulties with his
appropriation of Kant. The problems center on the Critical doctrine of Ideas of
Reason.
According to Kant, the
intellectual powers of the human mind have both a merely logical and a real
employment. In their merely logical employment, our rational capacities are used
to compare, contrast, order, and systematise such mental contents as they are
presented with, from whatever source. So the arrangement of objects of
perception by genera and species, the classification of sense—contents into the
familiar five senses, the rearrangement of judgments into the form of
syllogisms, and so forth, are all in—stances of the merely logical employment
of intelligence. Nothing is created thereby, and the result is no more than a
sorting out and neatening up of the materials presented to intelligence.
The real employment, on the other hand, is genuinely creative,
resulting in cognitively significant thoughts, or representations, as
Kant calls them, that did not exist
before, and could not have been arrived at by any process of the comparison,
reorganization, or abstraction from presented materials of consciousness.
In the CRITIQUE OF PURE
REASON, Kant differentiates between two intellectual powers of the mind, which
he labels Understanding and Reason. The real use of Understanding, he says,
produces the Pure Concepts of Understanding, or, as they are usually referred
to, the categories, among which are Substance and Accident, Cause and Effect,
Possibility, Necessity, and so forth.
Reason, personified by Kant as a
purposive agent, is said always to strive to complete the processes of
organization and arrangement which it undertakes in its merely logical
employment, seeking everywhere for the first cause in the series of causes, for
the necessary being on whose existence
rests the possibility of contingent beings, the first premise from which all syllogistic reasoning descends, and so forth.
Kant calls this the quest for the unconditioned, and he claims that the product
of the real employment of reason is the concept of the unconditioned.
For reasons of piety and historical pendulation [to use Harnack's lovely
neologism], Kant resurrects the Platonic term 'Idea,' and calls the various
articulations of the concept of unconditionality 'Ideas of reason.'
But though Kant talks this way all the time, he
offers no argument at all for the repeated invocation of Nature's purposes with
which the introductory and less central portions of his writings are filled. In
fact, of course, Kant himself, through his devastating refutations of the
traditional attempts at proving the existence of God, is, together with David
Hume, the Enlightenment executioner of this way of speaking. It is entirely
incompatible with the deeper teaching of the CRITIQUE to speak of the inner
coherence of tort law as though its achievement were an objectively necessary
task set us by the inner purposes of Reason itself. Rather, we must recognize
that ideal for what it is: one ideal among many that lawyers or theorists of
law may set for themselves, for their own political, aesthetic, moral, or
professional purposes.
So, in the
end, W.'s essay is little more than a cri de coeur, and Fletcher's
two—stage process of considerations of right followed by considerations of
humanity is as legitimate as any other. W's use of Kant here illustrates a more
general difficulty with the too—quick appropriation of portions of a
philosophy, as though they were bits and pieces of material that could be separated from the main body of
theory and bent to purposes of one's own. The philosophy of a great thinker
like Kant is an organic unity unfolding from one, or at most a very few,
central insights. One's understanding of every element in that philosophy,
however secondary or peripheral, is thoroughly conditioned by one's construal
of those central insights. Before we can 'use' the Kantian notion of an idea of
reason, for example, we must decide how we understand the revolutionary
teaching that concepts are rules for the organization of a diversity of
sense-contents, and hence have not even problematic application beyond the
limits of sense experience
W. cannot escape the necessity of stating, and
defending, his aesthetic, moral, political or professional reasons for seeking
internal coherence in the tort law, or in any other set of institutional
practices, for that matter. But this was simply the message of my opening
presentation. I guess it really was the
waste of time it seemed.
22 comments:
Keep those golden oldies coming......
That was a very nice read.
I'm especially fascinated with the part about Mary Gregor. Besides her work as a translator, I'm ashamed to say I knew nothing about her before you mentioned her here. Now I'm eager to learn more.
Bravo, Professor, a sublime example of Gonzo reporting. Hunter Thompson, had he survived the second barrel of that shotgun would, no doubt, be proud.
I loved this, but I'm surprised and disappointed that Prof. Wolff would stoop so low as to claim authorship. It's obviously written by P. G. Wodehouse; the only thing missing is the homily on the merits of the Empress of Blandings.
Alas, outed by John Rapko.
the world is 4 billion years old and we got to live at the same time as Professor Wolff; free to enjoy his incredible writing and lectures. What a blessing :)
HELP!!!
When I opened this blog link this morning, all of the text was in very small type--too small for me to read. That's not the case with any other blog I open, nor is it the case with the comment section of this blog--only Prof. Wolf's text--as of this morning.
Does anyone have a idea of what went wrong and how I could fix it?
With Google Chrome at least you can change the zoom on the text to increase the size. It's on the upper right side of your screen.
“[L]awyers, unlike serious philosophers [but, in this regard, quite like second–rate philosophers] [Ahem], do not actually seek to demonstrate the positions they defend. Rather, they aim to assimilate issues with which they are concerned to the existing structure of laws and precedents in hopes that courts will construe those issues in ways that favor their clients. For this purpose, lawyers need a large and versatile armamentarium of concepts, categories, distinctions, and argument fragments with the aid of which they can articulate intuitions, convictions, or interests to which they are already committed. … .”
What Prof. Wolff has written is largely true, but not as straightforward as it may sound. Different lawyers see and use that armamentarium in different ways. And to be a very good lawyer, the lawyer has to be able to think outside the box in order to see creative ways to use the tools in that armamentarium. And as has happened on previous occasions, Prof. Wolff’s post coincidentally intersects with my life. On Monday, March 15, I will be filing the most controversial lawsuit in my career. I am filing a lawsuit in federal court to undo a state court decision which was rendered five years ago, and which was affirmed by the Supreme Court of the state in which I practice – a very difficult thing to do. Moreover, what makes it even more controversial and difficult is that I am naming as a defendant in the lawsuit the judge who presided over the “trial” and rendered the judgment against my client. Naming a judge as a defendant rarely happens. This may be the first time that it has happened in my state. Why? Because judges have absolute immunity for the decisions they render in court – they cannot be sued for money damages. Moreover, they are also immune under the 11th Amendment, because they are employees of the state in which they preside, and under the 11th Amendment a citizen of a state cannot sue the state, any department of the state, or any employee of the state for damages in federal court. (If you read the 11th Amendment, you will note that is not at all what its says – it says that a citizen of one state cannot sue another state. But in a notorious decision, Hans v. Louisiana (1890), the Supreme Court ruled that the 11th Amendment also applies to citizens suing their own state.
(Continued)
So, given all this, why the hell am I doing this and how the hell can I expect to prevail? Because I have been thinking outside the box. And the facts of the case provide some illumination. My client had hired a home remodeling company that had an excellent reputation. She agreed to pay them x dollars in order to redo the electric wiring of her newly purchased home (it was a very old house and had antiquated knob and tube electric wiring, which is a fire hazard). The company was to do the rewiring, and while they were at it, replace the old insulation with new insulation. She was required to make a deposit of a substantial amount of money of ½ x, which she did. She was also required to purchase two permits from the city where she resides for both the electric and insulation work, which were paid for from the deposit. After the company claimed it had completed the insulation work, an inspector for the city gave the work a “pass,” meaning it had been done correctly. However, things between the company and my client began to break down because she was not satisfied with the quality of the work they were doing (e.g., they had to remove the baseboards in order to redo the wiring, but they broke and damaged the baseboards in the process, and tried to replace them with new baseboards which did not match the undamaged baseboards which they were going to reinstall). As part of the contract, she was told in an email that she did not have to pay the balance of the contract until it was done and she was satisfied. When things began to break down, the company demanded that she pay the balance of the contract, and she refused. So the company ordered the work crew to walk off the job, leaving the house with electric wires hanging out all over. The company then placed a construction lien on the home for the amount of the outstanding balance – and then they sued her for breach of contract.
In the meantime, my client (whom I will refer to as Jane) asked the chief inspector of the city to inspect the house, and he determined that, in fact, the insulation work had not been done. He poked a hole into one of the walls and, lo and behold, there was no insulation. But he refused to revoke the pass that his co-inspector had already issued. Jane had the misfortune to hire an attorney to represent her who did not know what the hell he was doing. For example, he filed a counter-complaint, but failed to include a claim that the construction company had breached the contract by walking off the job before the work was done. She also had the misfortune of drawing a very vindictive judge who is actually a bully in a black robe. Every motion that the company brought, he granted. And every motion that Jane’s attorney brought, he denied. For example, he would not allow him to amend his counter-complaint to add a claim of fraud, on the same day that he allowed the company’s attorney to add a claim of unjust enrichment. He then denied a motion by Jane’s attorney to add an expert witness to his witness list, because he filed it only two months before trial.
(Continued)
Three days before trial, Jane’s attorney gets cold feet and tells Jane that he wants to move to withdraw from the case because he does not have time to prepare for the trial. The judge ignores the motion. Then Jane files a motion to appear on her own behalf to represent herself. The judge ignores her motion as well. Comes the day of trial, Jane’s attorney does not appear, and nor does Jane, because she has not been given permission to represent herself. What does the judge do? He initially indicates to staff that he was going to adjourn the trial so that Jane could hire a new attorney, which would have been the fair and constitutional thing to do. However, because Jane’s mother appeared in court and was raising a ruckus about her daughter not having an attorney to represent her, the judge, out of vindictiveness, decided to go forward with the trial with only one side represented, empaneled a jury, and then entered a default judgment against Jane. He granted the company the outstanding balance on the contract, as well as their attorney fees, all of which added up to a pretty large chunk of money. Jane filed an appeal on her own, but because she does not have an attorney, the appellate court denies the appeal because she failed to cite any case authority in her brief. She then hires an attorney to seek leave to appeal to the state supreme court, which denies leave. At this point it all appears like things are over for Jane. She goes to several other attorneys to see if anything can be done, and they all tell her there is nothing that can be done. They cannot sue in federal court, they believe, because of two legal doctrines – the Rooker-Feldman doctrine, which holds you cannot sue in federal court to challenge a state court decision. Your only option is to appeal up the ladder through the state appellate courts, and then seek leave to appeal to the U.S. Supreme Court, which she did not do (the Supreme Court would not likely have granted leave in any case). And then there is another doctrine, called res judicata, which means you may not raise in another lawsuit claims which you did not raise, or could have raised, in a prior lawsuit. End of story.
After the judgment was entered, the company garnished Jane’s disability payments, in order to pay off the judgment – which was unlawful, because disability payments are exempt from garnishment. The company’s attorney then tried to sell the house in a sheriff’s sale to pay off the construction lien. Jane, the last minute obtained a loan to pay off the construction lien the day before the scheduled sheriff’s sale – but the company would not let her into their office to pay off the lien to avoid the sheriff’s sale. So Jane had to contact the sheriff’s office to force the company to allow the sheriff’s deputy into their office to pay off the lien and cancel the sheriff’s sale. The judge then appointed a receiver, who hired a property management company to lease another house that Jane owns in order to general rental income to pay off the judgment lien, which now only includes the attorney’s fees, which are increasing by the day because the fees accumulate interest. The tenants to whom the management company rent Jane’s other house damage the house and the property management company leaves the damage unrepaired.
(Continued)
Three weeks ago, Jane’s mother called me out of the blue because she saw my name on the internet relating to another lawsuit in which I am suing the city in question for violating the 1st Amendment right of freedom of religion of a number of residents (a story which I will forego explaining). I think she is calling to offer information about that lawsuit, and then she launches into this tale of woe regarding her daughter. I think, initially, this woman is a bit meshugenah, but decide to give her the benefit of the doubt because she tells me that her daughter owes so much money now that she is suicidal, and I am troubled by the fact that the judge proceeded to hold a trial when the defendant was not represented by counsel. I ask her to email me some documents. I then get inundated with several thousand pages of documents, including all of the witness depositions, all of the pre-trial hearing transcripts, the trial transcript itself, tons of emails, briefs, etc., etc.
So I start to review all of these documents and read all of the transcripts. And lo and behold, what do I find – I find that Jane had filed a complaint against the company with a state agency, and the state agency had issued a formal complaint against the company that had four counts. The first two counts accused the company of violating state law by claiming Jane had signed a five-page contract, which included exclusions of work they claim Jane agreed to, but she had in fact only signed the first page, because that was all she was given to sign. The second count charges that the contract was invalid because the company employee who negotiated the contract with Jane was not licensed. The last two counts charge the company with shoddy work. The company, I assume to avoid the expense of a long drawn out administrative proceeding, agrees to a Consent Order regarding the first two counts, and the last two counts are dismissed. Moreover, the president of the company signed a Stipulation – an admission of truth – that the document the company claims is the contract with Jane violated state law and is therefore null and void and unenforceable. And then I read the trial transcript in which Jane was not represented by an attorney - and lo and behold, I find the following: the company’s attorney had the president identify the five-page document as the contract with Jane, a document which he had agreed with the agency violated state law. The “contract” was marked as an exhibit and admitted by the judge – without the judge knowing that a state agency had ruled the contract violated state law! In so doing, the company – and its attorney – committed a fraud on the court, and the attorney had suborned (a fancy word for “induced”) perjury. Why is this important? Because fraud on the court is one of the exceptions to the Rooker-Feldman doctrine – you cannot go into federal court seeking to overturn a judgment in state court – unless you can prove that the judgment was obtained by fraud. And what about res judicata? That only applies if the claim you are making was raised, or could have been raised, in the prior state proceeding. But the issue of fraud was never raised, and was never adjudicated on, because the judge denied her attorney’s motion to amend the counter-complaint to include a claim of fraud.
(Continued)
So, on March 15, I will be filing a 75-page Complaint in federal court, containing 5 federal law and constitutional law claims, as well as 10 state law claims, to which will be attached 45 exhibits, asking that the Court rule that the judgment is null and void, because it was obtained by fraud on the state court and the subornation of perjury. I am also suing the city for violating Jane’s 5th and 14th Amendment rights because it required her to pay $350 for a permit to perform insulation work which a city inspector then issued a pass for, stating that the work had been done when it had not been done, a pass which was offered as an exhibit at the trial to prove that the company had done the insulation work and that Jane was violating the contract by refusing to pay for work which they claim had been done, but which had not been done. By requiring Jane to buy a permit which entailed that a city inspector would have to approve the work, but then the inspector gave a pass for work which had not been done, the city essentially took Jane’s $350 without providing the service that the payment is for, which constitutes an unconstitutional “taking” under the 5th Amendment and a deprivation of property without due process under the 14th Amendment. I am also suing the judge for violating Jane’s 1st Amendment right of access to the courts, and her 14th Amendment right to procedural due process, for proceeding to hold a jury trial without the defendant being represented by an attorney, rather than adjourning the trial to allow Jane to hire a new attorney, and that he did so out of vindictiveness, retaliating against Jane because he was pissed off at Jane’s mother. And no, I am not suing the judge for money, because he is immune, but I am suing under an exception to the 11th Amendment which allows a citizen of a state to sue an officer of the state not for damages, but for declaratory or injunctive relief, i.e., I am asking the federal court to issue a ruling – a declaratory judgment – that by proceeding to trial with a litigant not present and not represented by an attorney, he violated Jane’s constitutional rights. When I file this lawsuit on Monday, and the press gets hold of it, all hell will break loose – and there will be one very angry state court judge. And by the way, I am not charging Jane a cent; she only has to pay for the court costs – filing fee, deposition costs, etc. I just want to make sure that this travesty of justice gets reversed.
So, yes, attorneys apply an armamentarium of concepts, categories, etc. to try to obtain justice for their clients, but some attorneys are better at using those tools than others, and it takes inventiveness, creativity and diligence to use them to the client’s best advantage.
s. wallerstein
Thanks very much. That worked.
David Palmeter,
Great!
Post-script:
If you have read this far, you may be thinking, “Why doesn’t Jane just sue her former attorney for legal malpractice for not showing up at the trial? Can’t she recover form him all of her damages, since he caused them?” Well, she has retained another attorney to sue her former attorney – except her former attorney did not have legal malpractice insurance and therefore is probably uncollectible. Her attorney suing her former attorney had declined to try to get the judgment overturned, because he saw no way to do it. Enter Samuel Chase.
Sammy, baby, stop discrediting yourself with these over-long Comments. Every one already knows that you're some kind of legalistic genius. You need not keep attempting to prove it--- rather undermines you're thrust actually.
Jeffrey,
As usual, you missed my point. As Brian Leiter pointed out in his essay, “Disagreement, Anti-Realism About Reasons, And Inferences To The Best Explanations,” the first-rate philosophers have been arguing among themselves for several hundred years about what constitutes reasons for action, without any resolution. He ends the essay stating, “the history of philosophy .. is the history of intractable dispute about reasons for acting.” (Footnote omitted.)
While the first-rate philosopher have been engaged in this “intractable dispute,” the second-rate philosophers – the lawyers – have been dealing with the real problems of everyday life – prosecuting criminals and putting them away from the rest of society; defending the purported criminals from the transgression of over-zealous prosecutors; representing clients against people who have taken their property, defamed them, violated their constitutional rights, used excessive force to arrest them, etc., etc. Now, I have a high regard for the first-rate philosophers – I once aspired to be one of them – but I settled for being a second-rate philosopher so that I could help people deal with the problems confronting them in their everyday life – obtaining the government benefits they are entitled to; undoing an unjust verdict; fighting the discrimination they have been exposed to at work because of their race, or their gender, or their religion, or their age; and getting them acquitted from being convicted for a crime that could not be proved they committed beyond a reasonable doubt - something which takes a first-rate lawyer to do successfully, and something I doubt any first-rate philosopher could have done.
I'm of two minds about posting this actually, but in case anyone is interested my review of K. Forrester's In the Shadow of Justice is up at the blog of the Society for U.S. Intellectual History:
https://s-usih.org/2021/03/review-of-in-the-shadow-of-justice/
L. F. Cooper,
In light of my comment above, I may just purchase “In The Shadow Of Justice,” just to read the chapter titled, “The Limits of Philosophy.”
@ S. Chase
I realize you're being humorous. My non-humorous response is that while I doubt that that particular chapter wd meet yr expectations, you might nonetheless find the book worth buying (in the paperback edition).
If you are hurt in an accident, it is important to contact an experienced personal injury attorney as soon as possible, so that Witnesses and evidence don't disappear. At the Law Offices of Alexander M. Gurevich PC, we will work hard to maximize the compensation for your harms and losses.
Post a Comment