Thirty years ago, I wrote a lengthy essay based in part on what I had learned from a book by Edwin Wilmsen called LAND FILLED WITH FLIES. I have broken it down into three parts of roughly equal length and over the next several days will post it here on this blog. I would be very interested in any responses that readers have to it.
A Critique of the Concept of Culture
Introduction
Let
me begin by stating the thesis of this paper, so that you know where I am
headed. I maintain that the concept of culture, as it has come to be used in
Anthropological writings, in theoretical treatments of contemporary social
questions, and in popular discussions of such issues as multi-culturalism [in
the United States] and the formation of a national culture [in South Africa],
is fundamentally confused. It obscures rather reveals the truth about social
formations, and works ideologically to conceal from view the political and
economic interests of relatively powerless or disadvantaged sectors of society.
Hence, I argue, the term "culture" is theoretically misleading and
political reactionary. It should be replaced, in our vocabulary, by such terms
as "class" and "politics." If I am correct, then we ought
not to embrace proposals for "cultural autonomy," for "multi-cultural
education," or for the creation of a "national culture of
liberation," even when these are advanced by spokespersons of manifestly
oppressed groups who experience their own political or economic oppression as a
denial of their traditional and authentic culture.
Your
first reaction to this thesis may be that it is surely too bold to be true! How
can a concept employed so widely and with such evident conviction be so
completely lacking in theoretical legitimacy? Leaving to one side the obvious
rejoinder, namely that the corresponding thesis is manifestly true for every
system of religious concepts, let me somewhat reassure you by saying that there
is, of course, a legitimate and quite non-tendentious sense of
"culture" that suffers none of the ideological disabilities that I am
trying to expose. But, as I shall try to show you a bit later on, it has proved
fatally easy to slide from that unproblematic notion of culture to the highly
problematic, ideologically charged notion.
So
much for where I am going. Let me start where I started nine months ago in my
graduate seminar, with Land Filled With Flies, Edwin Wilmsen's critique
of the ethnographic work of the American anthropologist Richard Lee. I shall
try to lead you, step by step, along the path l myself took, until finally I am
able to formulate and argue for my thesis in a suitably general way.
I
should say, by way of explanation, that my decision to begin with a lengthy
discussion of a text devoted to a quite specific and limited subject matter is
deliberate, and reflects my long-held conviction that the best theoretical
generalizations arise out of, and must remain rooted in, substantive, factually
rich analyses of specific social or historical situations. I reject completely
the sort of abstract, programmatic writing that proceeds at a level so elevated
and rarefied that one quickly loses all sense of what is really at stake -
writing in which "post-modern," "intertextual,"
"inscribed," and "discourse" are repeated talismanically,
and in which a passing reference to Western Civilization is considered grubbing
with the data.
I
might have come to my conclusions about the concept of culture in any of
a dozen ways, but the fact is that I arrived at them by reading and thinking
about Wilmsen's book, and that is therefore where I have chosen to begin.
1.
Wilmen’s
Critique of Richard Lee
In Land
Filled With Flies, Wilmsen argues that a large group of very sophisticated
and professionally highly regarded anthropologists are in the grip of an
ideologically distorting conception of human history and society that has
thoroughly blinded them to the plain evidence in front of their faces, with the
consequence that they have substituted, for accurate description and analysis,
a fable of the Primitive Hunter-Gatherer - a fable that they have projected
onto a group of people living at the current time in a portion of the Northern
Kalahari. According to Wilmsen, these anthropologists - Richard Lee and his
associates - have misconstrued the history, the political economy, the social
structure, and even the sheer biology of the people in question, despite
the fact that they have carried out extensive and broad-based field
observations over a period of several decades. Wilmsen further believes that
this ideological distortion has led Lee and his associates to embrace
substantive policy proposals that are oppressive of, and unjust to, the people
in question.
Building
on this critique, Wilmsen suggests that the fault lies not with Lee, but with
ethnography itself. In the Introduction to Land Filled With Flies, he
writes: ''This book is ... not an ethnography. One of its major premises is
that the ethnographic era of anthropology, an era marked by the excision of
societies from their historical contexts, is behind us - we may hope never to
return." [p. xii]
To
see the connection between this attack on ethnography and the concept of
culture, we can remind ourselves of Emile Durkheim's methodological
justification of sociology as an autonomous discipline. "Indubitably for
sociology to be possible," he writes in Suicide, "it must
above all have an object all its own. It must take cognizance of a reality that
is not in the domain of the other sciences. But if no reality exists outside of
individual consciousness, it wholly lacks any material of its own. In that
case, the only possible subject of observation is the mental states of the
individual, since nothing else exists.... [T]here can be no sociology unless
societies exist, and ... societies cannot exist if there are only
individuals. [Preface, emphasis in the original.]
Culture
is to ethnography
what Society is to sociology. It is the autonomous object of study, not
reducible to objects in the domain of any other discipline, the existence of
which legitimates ethnography as an authentic independent discipline. When
Wilmsen denies that his work is an ethnography, and expresses the deliberately
provocative hope that the ethnographic era of anthropology has ended, never to
return, he can only be understood as implicitly asserting that the concept of
culture, on which ethnography is founded, is irretrievably flawed. Wilmsen's
disclaimer thus has powerful and far-reaching implications.
A. The
Theoretical Background
As anthropology came into existence as an
organized discipline in the nineteenth century, it replaced the early credulous
retailing of golden age myths and accounts of weird and wonderful peoples and
practices with more disciplined accounts. [Although the notion lingered of anthropologists
as sophisticated, highly educated representatives of advanced western society
who make long, difficult, taxing, but exciting adventures to far away places
-which is to say, places far away from western Europe or the United States-
where they encounter and study primitive peoples.] The original notion of the
primitive as the Edenic stage of natural ma was replaced by an evolutionary
account of the development of Homo Sapiens from "lower" life forms.
The historical account of human civilization,
based on investigations into ancient documents, inscriptions on clay tablets or
stones, and archeological cross-checking of Biblical or Epic narratives,
established something like a continuous narrative that takes us back perhaps
ten thousand years. But archeological excavations and modern techniques of the
dating of organic materials revealed that Homo Sapiens, as a biological
species, had existed in unaltered physical, and hence presumably unaltered
genetic, form for at least a hundred thousand years. Excavations of
pre-historic sites made it extremely likely that groups of biological humans
had long bad socially transmitted religious and other practices, and probably
language as well.
Excavations of sites 6,000 to 10,000 years
old produced the remains of what can only be construed as cities, the size,
complexity, and manner of construction of which compel us to posit a rather
elaborate social and political structure capable of mobilizing the labor of
large numbers of people performing differentiated and integrated functions
[stone masons, hauling-sled designers and builders, quarriers, builders and
sailors of ships]. Such labor in turn presupposes a division of function that
assigns to some people the task of producing more food than they need for themselves,
the remainder being used to feed those who are doing the labor of city
building, and so forth. The archeological evidence suggests strongly that the
economic key to the emergence of cities is the domestication of animals and the
initiation of large-scale farming - what anthropologists call the Neolithic
Revolution.
More recent fieldwork and theoretical
reinterpretations have somewhat blurred the distinction between the foraging
stage of human development and the stage characterized by domestication of
animals and farming, but it remains the case that anyone looking backward from
the present day sees the following picture: a very long period, perhaps 100,000
years or more, during which there is little or no evidence of any major change
in the way Homo Sapiens live, followed by a rather brief period of historical
time during which there is ever more rapid technological, social, intellectual,
and political change, bringing us by dint of an explosion of material changes
in the past two centuries to our present situation.
This reconstruction poses two very difficult
questions: First, and most obviously, what explains the rapid change of the
past ten millennia, particularly of the past two centuries? And Second, not so
obviously, but more fundamentally, what explains the total absence of change in
the period ten times as long before that?
The most powerful and influential answer to
the first question - that of Karl Marx - is that the locus of historical change
is the class structure of a society. Taking over Hegel's notion of historical
periodization, Marx early in his life put forward the thesis that the story of
human history is essentially the story of progressively more advanced division
of labor, with the consequent class struggles between those who control, and
those who do not control, the means of production. For historians, this has
proved to be a very successful hypothesis, with whose use they can organize a
great deal of historical data and work out explanations of a wide variety of
important historical events - the decline and fall of the Roman Empire, the
development of medieval feudalism, the English Civil War, the French
Revolution, the American Revolution, the American Civil War, and so on.
But to an ethnographer, this hypothesis seems
to imply a rather striking answer to the second question concerning the
apparent lack of change in the pre-history of the human species. Human groups
in that earlier time - tribes, bands, clans, or whatever one wishes to call
them - must have exhibited no internal division of labor, nor any class
structure based upon differential ownership of the means of production.
Non-human animals live and reproduce in more
or less successful adaptive relation to their environment. As the environment
changes - water becomes more or less available, food sources vary, climate
changes - those species adapt in ways that come, over very long periods of
time, to become encoded in their genetic make-up.
But in human groups, social structure
substitutes for species adaptation as the mediating element between individuals
and nature. Men and women produce their conditions of existence by purposeful
action, and we must appeal to the social fact of differential ownership of the
means of production to explain how, and how well, they do this. The social
comes to interpose itself between the psychological and the natural as a third,
autonomous category of existence. And - for rather complex reasons
about which 1 shall have a good deal to say a bit later on - this
interposition of social structure between the individual and nature carries
with it necessarily, inevitably, the historicity of the human condition. Elephants
do not have a history; neither do dolphins, so far as we know. But humans do,
because they produce and reproduce the class structures that organize their
production, in the process of becoming human and living out their lives.
Thus, the reconstructed story of a lengthy
ahistorical period of changeless repetitive reproduction followed by a
relatively short burst of unilinear historical development is explained by
postulating a long period of human band or group adaptation to the natural
environment unmediated by internal class structure, followed by an as yet
unexplained emergence of property relations and class structure, giving rise to
history.
This part of the story is marked by a rather
arcane, but important, debate over the concept of labor in the writings
of Marx. The debate turns on the distinction between subjects and instruments
of labor. Briefly, from the point of view of a twentieth century European
or American anthropologist who drives up to his research site in a Land Rover,
unpacks his lightweight Nylon tent, sets up his camp stove, and prepares to do
a little high-tech camping while recording his ethnographic observations on
film, tape, and Laptop, it must appear that the Zhu are in virtually unmediated
contact with their natural surroundings, foraging for food in much the same
directly adaptive manner that the higher mammals of the Serengeti do. To be
sure, they have a few pots and arrows, and bits and snatches of clothing, but
material nature seems to serve them as the mere subject of their labor, that on
which their labor operates. There do not seem to be instruments of labor that
are interposed between them and nature, by the deployment and use of which they
transform nature so as to serve their needs. They range across their territory,
picking up nuts or berries as they find them, just as monkeys do; they run down
Gemsbok in packs, following the wounded animals for days until they drop,
rather than building brakes and pens, or cultivating them, as the Lapps do with
their reindeer, for example.
Wilmsen completely rejects this view. In the
form of a debate about the proper interpretation of several passages in Capital,
he argues against distinguishing the productive efforts of foragers from
those of herdsmen or farmers. After several pages of textual exegesis, Wilmsen
writes:
Finally, it seems clear to me that - if the reading of
Marx's placement of Paleolithic peoples I offer above us accepted - Marx
included forager relations to instruments of production and to land among those
of other humans.... From this formulation it seems to me inescapable that to
segregate a foraging mode of production on the basis of land as a subject of
labor is to deny full humanity to modern "foragers," a
nineteenth-century notion subscribed to neither by Marx nor by any of the
modern proponents of such a mode of production. On these ontological grounds,
it appears that current constructions of a forager mode of production are
irretrievably flawed and must be abandoned. [Wilmsen, p. 49]
So
the historical change of the past ten millennia or so is explained by Marx as
resulting from the inner workings of the conflicts that arise, within the
processes of production and distribution, over control of the product, and most
particularly of the surplus product over and above what is required simply to
keep the production process going from cycle to cycle and generation to
generation. And anthropologists like Lee conclude that pre-historic human
beings must have lacked any class structure mediating the process of production
and reproduction.
Pre-historic
human beings, they speculated, could only be thought of as living in a
symbiotic relationship with their environment - not productively transforming
it, but living off it, as impala or elephant have on the Serengeti Plain for
hundreds of thousands of years. Small bands of humans, they postulated, hunted
wild animals and gathered such foods as grew naturally. They were, in short,
Hunter-Gatherers.
[It
is worth pointing out, by way of illustrating the extent to which ideological
considerations shape scientific theories, that the "hunter-gatherer"
model is a politically correct revision of the original "patriarchal"
theoretical construct of Man the Hunter. The first construction of the
pre-historic, post-hominid stage of human development assigned productive
functions - hunting - to the men, and reproductive functions - bearing and rearing
children - to the women. Anthropologists explained, in suitably scientific
fashion, that the long maturation stage of the human infant made it impossible
for women to participate in the economic activities of the primitive horde. All
of this was tricked out with elaborate stories about the adaptive monogamous
mating strategies of the primitive male, who was portrayed as a loving, caring,
bread-winning pater familias, roughly along the lines of a middle-class
Victorian husband. This unacceptable bit of sexist science gave way to the more
appropriate model of the two-wage-earner family in which women were construed
as gatherers of nuts and berries, and men as hunters of wild animals. Hence
"hunter- gatherer."]
Now
then: All of this was in the nature of a purely theoretical reconstruction,
buttressed by archeological evidence derived from the excavation of campsites,
burial grounds, caves, and such like.
Imagine
the extraordinary excitement that anthropologists experienced when they heard
that there were still groups of human beings living TODAY in this same
pre-historic fashion! Primitive hunter-gatherers living out the age-old
patterns, far away in remote corners of the world so removed from modern
settlements, trade routes, and even voyages of exploration that somehow they
have been left behind by history! In the Outback of Australia, in the farthest
reaches of the Kalahari, in the depths of the Amazon rain forest, the reports
came back of the last remnants of extremely primitive peoples who neither
domesticated animals nor farmed, but lived by ranging over their environment
like herds of mammals, hunting and gathering.
To
study such peoples, one can easily imagine oneself thinking, would be, in
effect, to travel back in time, for if the practices of such peoples had not
changed from 100,000 years ago to 50,000 years ago, or from 50,000 years ago to
10,000 years ago, perhaps they had also not changed from 10,000 years ago to
the present. Perhaps, we can imagine them thinking, if we pack up our gear and
hurry to the Outback or the Kalahari, we can actually see people
indistinguishable from their unimaginably ancient ancestors. Perhaps we can
learn their languages, capture them on film and tape, study their tools and
techniques, and thus acquire, through direct observation and access, a firm
foundation for a complete theory of human history, by ascertaining the
condition of the human race before the march of history began.
This,
more or less explicitly, was the motivation for the massive efforts by Lee and
his associates to study the living daylights out of the people whom they call
the Dobe !Kung before assimilation had completely wiped out the last traces of
pre-history.
Since
my exposition of their theoretical perspective can hardly be called neutral,
let me say a word in defense of Lee and his coworkers before turning to
Wilmsen's critique. They are not fools, nor are they at all unimaginative. They
were aware from the very first that the Zhu stood in rather extensive social,
economic, and even political relationships with other peoples in their region,
including the Herero, various European colonial powers, and the South African
government. Indeed, it was this awareness that lent urgency to their work, for
they could see these interactions - which they conceived as outside
influences - almost daily diminishing the purity, and hence the
significance to them, of the pristine hunter-gatherer mode of life among the
Zhu.
We
should also note that Lee conceived himself to be taking a politically
progressive position with regard to the treatment of the Zhu by the governments
of Botswana and South Africa. In the context of American politics, he was in
theory and in practice very far to the left. The dispute between Wilmsen and
Lee is not a standard fight between left and right, by any means. This
by way of a warning not to read too simple-minded an interpretation into the
dispute.
So far, it seems to me that "hunter-gatherer" is a purely descriptive designation: i.e., that's what these people did, they hunted and gathered (or foraged). The "ideological" way in which this label distorts or "dehumanizes" the people to whom it's applied is not yet really clear, at least not to me, but maybe will become so as the paper continues.
ReplyDeleteIt also seems to me there's some blurring here between the notions of social structure and class structure. Hunter-gatherers might not have had a discernible class structure, certainly not one based on ownership (or lack thereof) of the means of production, but they did have some kind of social structure. But then lions and gazelles etc. also have a kind of social structure. So no group, whether of humans or non-human animals, stands in a completely "unmediated" relation to the natural world. Rousseau's solitary "savage," assuming he existed (which is likely dubious), might have stood in an unmediated relation to the natural environment, but he's not being discussed in the paper.
"Homo Sapiens, as a biological species, had existed in unaltered physical, and hence presumably unaltered genetic, form for at least a hundred thousand years..."
ReplyDeleteThe problem with explaining this scientific evidence to the masses is that it takes higher educational institutions & many years of education under such institutions to explain it all. If people are uneducated in such matters they have just as much proof on any other theory that they are willing or motivated to buy into.
Not a substantive comment but a question: do you plan to upload the whole talk to your OneDrive?
ReplyDeleteI will put it in "my stuff" accessible from this blog. Is that the same thing?
ReplyDeleteSome quotes from RPW's text:
ReplyDelete“Briefly, from the point of view of a twentieth century European or American anthropologist who drives up to his research site in a Land Rover, unpacks his lightweight Nylon tent, …"
“… it must appear that the Zhu are in virtually unmediated contact with their natural surroundings, foraging for food in much the same directly adaptive manner that the higher mammals of the Serengeti do …“
“They range across their territory, picking up nuts or berries as they find them, just as monkeys do …"
“Pre-historic human beings, they speculated, could only be thought of as living in a symbiotic relationship with their environment - not productively transforming it, but living off it, as impala or elephant have on the Serengeti Plain for hundreds of thousands of years …“
I must unfortunately admit that I have neither read "Land filled with flies" nor "Man the Hunter". Not least for this reason I would be interested to know whether the passages quoted above from RPW's text are polemical exaggerations or whether Lee and his collaborators actually went so far as to equate humans with animals in terms of their behavior before the so-called "Neolithic Revolution"?
Regardless of this, it seems to me that the scientific equipment in the study of prehistoric epochs of human development today no longer consists only of a nylon tent, gas stove and laptop. There are probably not many sciences that need to be as interdisciplinary as these researchers. Biologists, geneticists, geologists, climatologists and anthropologists work together with physicists, forensic scientists and many other faculties. Even criminologists are sometimes involved, as in the case of the discovery of the so-called "Ötzi" https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/%C3%96tzi
"Living off" an environment, as animals do, is not the same as bring in an "unmediated" relationship with that environment. The relation of a pride of lions to its environment, for instance, is "mediated" by the relations (of dominance and subordination or whatever) that exist within the pride. Or so I'd suggest (w.o being an ethologist or any kind of natural scientist).
ReplyDeleteYou might say this is a purely semantic point, but its significance is that a group of animals does not nec. represent a baseline of "primitiveness" from which the "productive transformation" of an environment by humans is necessarily a giant step forward. The domestication of some animals, agriculture, and urbanization allowed humans to create civilizations that not only produced art and philosophy but also facilitated slavery, famines, epidemics, and organized cruelty. Whether this was progress or whether most people would have remained happier picking up nuts and berries may be an open question.
P.s. though it was not of course an open question for Marx, for whom each successive mode of production represents an advance over the preceding one.
ReplyDeleteI know nothing about anthropology, but if I had to decide which portrayal of a society I had never been to was accurate and I had no means of going there myself, I would read all the material on that society that was available before opting for one portrayal and I certainly would not decide on philosophical, ideological or political grounds.
ReplyDeleteReality is very tricky and seldom is courteous enough to conform to one's philosophical, ideological or political convictions.
s.. wallerstein is correct that reality in general, in regarding human nature and social norms in particular, is often unpredictable and difficult to discern. Sometime in the 1970’s I saw a documentary on TV about a tribe in Africa, known as the Ik (yes, Ik) people which portrayed them as extremely selfish people, lacking in any sense of empathy for others. They were extremely poor, suffering from mass starvation. The documentary asserted that Ik mothers lacked typical maternal instincts, that they abandoned their children to starve, and that members of the tribe competed for food, which they refused to share. The message was supposed to be that humans are not naturally cooperative and empathic, that when social norms break down, they become uncivilized and brutish. The New York Times ran an article about them, written by Christopher Lehmanna-Haupt, based on information provided by physician/science journalist, Lewis Thomas and anthropologist Colin Turnbull, who had written a book about the Ik, titled “The Mountain People,” in which he portrayed them as, “the loveless people” and as “unfriendly, uncharitable, inhospitable and generally mean as any people can be.” Turnbull was so disgusted by the Ik culture (or, according to him, lack of culture), that he recommended to the Ugandan government that they be rounded up and sent to remote parts of Uganda where they could have not contact with other humans.
ReplyDeleteAs it turns out, none of what was said and written about the Ik was accurate, and was based on faulty research. You can read about it at the link below.
https://aeon.co/essays/why-were-the-ik-people-vilified-as-selfish-and-nasty
Drawing broad conclusions from a single synchronic study (especially in a colonial/post colonial context) seems like malpractice.
ReplyDelete