WHY
INDEED
by
Johannes Climacus
Responsible for publication
Robert Paul Wolff
1
The Workshop in Kantian Legal
Theory, of which the papers reproduced here are a partial record, was a curious
event, withal. Nineteen men and one woman, closeted - and cossetted - for three
days in Columbia University's Arden House for the avowed purpose of discussing
the jurisprudential theories of the greatest philosopher who ever lived,
Immanuel Kant. Fifteen hundred dollars plus expenses for the six authors of the
papers circulated in advance for discussion, five hundred for those charged
with participating in the discussion, the bill to be paid by the right-wing
Liberty Fund, whose minatory representative, eerily resembling the Jehovah's
Witnesses who every day radiate from their home in Brooklyn Heights to proselytize
the faith, attended each session to make sure that the hired hands put in a
full day's work.
Five of the nineteen were
professional philosophers, four of them Kant scholars who had made their
reputations struggling with one or another of Kant's great works. Twelve hours
of concentrated discussion on Kant's philosophy was, in Eliza
Doolittle's words, mother's milk to them, and Philosophy being what it is, the
pay wasn't bad either. But the remaining fourteen were professors of law - two
from Canada, one from England, a lone representative of the German Federal
Republic, and the rest from the United States. What, one could not help but
wonder, were they doing there? What could Kant possibly have to say to them
that would justify three days of unrelenting Kantshtick?
2
vocation of his name was code for
intensely felt hostility to unspecified, but dangerously lax, tendencies in
modern legal thinking. Re seemed to draw strength from even garbled allusions
to significant texts in Kant's ethical writings.
Most voluble of the nineteen was
Fletcher's colleague, Bruce Ackerman, brilliant, precocious, enormously — and
on occasion, with some justification — pleased with himself. Antaeus—like,
Ackerman would draw renewed strength from the sound of his own voice, so that
launched upon a comment of finite scope, he would be refreshed by his words,
and extend his remarks to fill all available space and time. Competing with
Ackerman for the floor most often was the radical philosopher and sometime Kant
scholar Robert Paul Wolff, whose face, contorted by a persistant facial tic,
showed excitement, disgust, irritation, and exasperation in quick succession.
Ackerman and Wolff, like the two youngest boys at a Seder, frequently competed
to see who could ask the most questions from a reclining position, both of them
manifestly expecting an indulgent Jewish mother to pat them on the head and offer
them another piece of cake.
Intervening
with impassioned criticisms that often outran their target somewhat was
newly—tenured Andrzej Rapaczynski, also of Columbia Law School. Rapaczynski,
quite possibly the philosophically quickest mind at the conference, had many
years earlier been a brilliant student in the Columbia philosophy department,
and had studied with Wolff. Now that he is safely tenured, it can perhaps be
acknowledged that Rapaczynski is really a philosopher, not a Jurisprude,
and in his youthful enthusiasm he was frequently less successful than his
fellow philosophers in concealing his dismay at the appallingly low level of
understanding of Kant manifested around the table.
Across from Ackerman and Wolff sat
tall, thin Mary Gregor, bent in a
3
question mark of deference to her neighbor, Douglas
Dryer, a long—time Kant scholar from Canada. As the only real expert present on
the subject of the conference — she is the author of the major commentary on
the work under discussion — Gregor was of course almost silent during the three
days. Genuine technical knowledge was in short supply, and would, if too often
displayed, have tended to inhibit the free flow of conversation.
Casting something of a
pall on the proceedings was Professor Dr. Wolfgang Naucke of Frankfurt
University, a Professor of Law and a Judge. For Naucke, it appeared, Kant
constitutes the last barrier separating western civilization from barbarism,
although whether from the left or from the right remained for a while
unclear. Naucke's discussion of Kant was couched in a grammatical mode that
might be dubbed the incantatory imperative, inspiring in the listener
contradictory impulses to cheer and salute. Naucke's true colors were revealed
almost by accident, midway through the discussion of his paper. Asked directly
and flatly whether he considered Kant's jurisprudence incompatible with the welfare
state, he replied, laconically, yes. At that, Wolff, who had been dozing, sat
bolt upright like the dormouse at the Mad Hatter's tea party and confessed
himself suddenly to have recaptured an interest in the proceedings.
In striking contrast to Naucke, Herbert Morris, Dean
of Humanities at UCLA, brought a welcome touch of laid—back California cool to
the conference, taking the sting out of the Morningside Heights intensity of
Ackerman, Rapaczynski, et al. Morris is well known for his philosophical
discussions of the theory of punishment, and had in previous years carried on a
debate in the literature on that subject with one of the Kant scholars present,
Jeffrie Murphy of Arizona State. Prompted by a question during the discussion
of Murphie's paper, Morris treated the conference to an exquisite illustration
of how to expound a systematic philosophical position while ap‑
4
peering merely to reminisce about an experience on a
California freeway. Morris' impromptu remarks were one of the few moments of
genuine style in an otherwise pedestrian three days.
The
non—Canadian North Americans around the table were intermittently chivvied,
with ironic deprecation, by crypto—Thomist Ernest Weinrib from the University
of Toronto. Weinrib, and his killer rabbit sidekick Peter Benson from McGill,
were the only lawyers at the conference who appeared seriously to be interested
in the substance of the law. Weinrib's complaint, the internal incoherence of
tort law south of his border, and the contrasting beauty and elegance of
Canadian tort law, utterly mystified the philosophers around the table, but
appeared to be an old familiar tune to the other lawyers.
As Spinoza noted, the
self comes to know itself only as it sees itself reflected in others. Hence
lovers need the beloved, actors crave audiences, and professors tolerate
students. Fletcher, understanding these needs, had, like a good host, provided
a symbolic student presence in the form of the editorial board of the Columbia
Law Journal. They were of course enjoined from interrupting the heavenly
discourses by juvenile interventions, but they were permitted to be present at
the proceedings, with the understanding that they would in due course turn over
the pages of their journal to the finished products.
5
intercourse]. The students, all of whom had done
philosophy either as graduates or as undergraduates, were in a state of
shocked dismay, quite well aware of the philosophical shambles unfolding before
them, and unable to imagine how they could in good conscience feed the
audience of their journal so thin a gruel.
And there they all were, removed from the distractions
of Manhattan, fed and cared for by a silent, efficient Arden House staff,
serenaded by a chamber trio on the second evening, and embarked on twelve hours
of investigation Of the Rechtslehre, Part One of Kant's late, minor
work, THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS.
Each
two-hour session was devoted to one of the prepared papers, which
all conference participants had received in advance. Robert Paul Wolff led off
on the first afternoon. Wolff, accustomed to the terse prose style of the
philosophical world, and mistakenly expecting to have to read his paper aloud,
had been well along in the drafting of eighteen or twenty carefully crafted
pages when a chance phone call to Fletcher had revealed that the other
participants were producing 'fifty to eighty pages.' Panicked by the potential
mortification of showing up with the shortest paper on the block, Wolff
discarded his draft and began again. Since the paper was intended for non-philosophers, he reasoned, a fair
amount of space could usefully be devoted to teaching them something about
Kant. Having written two books on Kant's philosophy, and having taught Kant for
thirty years, Wolff found it no great strain to churn out fifty pages in the
next four days, and it was this effort that the conferees had all read. [Wolff
was inordinately pleased with his effort, and much excited by the prospect of
publishing a fifty-page paper in the Columbia Law Journal. The students, not
fooled for a moment, spoke many kind words to him but chose not to publish.]
The gravamen of Wolff's effort
was that just as Kant's moral philosophy
6
has
to be read in the light of the deeper doctrines of the CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON,
in which context it becomes clear that there are fundamental contradictions
between the two which mortally undermine the moral philosophy, so too Kant's
legal philosophy must be interpreted through its relation to Kant's fundamental
epistemological teachings, with equally disastrous consequences. The
implication of Wolff's remarks was that the Kantian legal philosophy was
without defensible foundation. Consequently, although the session was
pronounced a great success, and was said to have started the conference off in
fine style, Wolff's argument was henceforth completely ignored.
A
break for drinks and dinner, and the participants returned, fueled and
lubricated, for an evening discussion of Fletcher's 89 page note. Fletcher's
paper bearing only a parametric relation to Kant, there was considerable
hermeneutical space between object—text and subject—discourse within which an
unfettered conversation could develop, and everyone pitched in with enthusiasm.
And so it went for two more days.
The next morning, Naucke's apocalyptic warnings were followed by Weinrib's animadversions,
with Murphy's scholarly and professional addendum to his well—known writings on
Kant's retributive theory of punishment preparing the group for the chamber
music to follow. The conference was brought to a close with an elegantly
evasive defense, by the cultivated Oxford homophobe John Finnis, of his utterly
appalling paper. David Richards, a
principal target of Finnis' crabbed and ungenerous remarks, conducted himself
with a restraint that was made all the more effective by the eloquence of his
reply. The Finnis session was graced by the one moment of genuine scholarship:
in rebuttal of Finnis' implausible attempt to claim Kant's support for his own
sectarian views, Mary Gregor,
7
2 comments:
Professor, this is hilarious.
I agree. I laughed out loud at the suggestion that citing Kant boosts your hit points.
Post a Comment