The subject of today's disquisition is relative exploitation. This
is not the taking advantage of your cousin, as you might imagine. The term was invented by Marxists trying to
make sense of something that Marx got wrong.
Recall that when Marx wrote in the early and middle nineteenth century,
he believed that he was looking at two complementary developments in the
evolution of capitalism that would, in their interaction, eventually lead to a
socialist revolution.
The first development was the progressive merger of many
small capitals into larger and larger firms.
Competition, Marx was convinced, would lead large capitalist firms to
drive smaller capitalist firms to the wall.
Although the story of the last century is complex, Marx's intuition was
essentially correct. We live now in a
world dominated by enormous multi-national corporations whose accumulations of
capital dwarf even that of small nations.
Marx was also convinced that the displacement of traditional
crafts first by the gathering of craftsmen into manufactories and then by the substitution
of machinery for hand-crafting ["manu-facturing"] would progressively
reduce the working class to a mass of easily substitutable semi-skilled workers
who could with relatively little difficulty be shifted from one line of
machine-tending to another as the forces of competition and supply and demand
dictated. There is no doubt that this
process was under way when Marx was writing, and as Harry Braverman documents
in a classic study, Labor and Monopoly
Capital, the process continued well into the twentieth century.
However, the evolution of the working class has proceeded in
a manner not anticipated by Marx. What
we find now in the capitalist world is stable, entrenched hierarchies of
wage-and-salary earning workers whose work experiences, compensation, and life
chances are so varied that nothing remotely resembling working-class solidarity
has been able to develop and grow. From
a purely formal perspective, both the men and women who work on the
loading-dock or the assembly line and the middle managers in suits who occupy
the corner offices are wage-earning
employees who do not owe their positions to ownership or control of the
means of production, and who must sell their labor to live.
The labor force of a modern capitalist nation is segmented
in a number of ways, by gender, by race, by age, and by educational
credentials, none of which, not even the last of these, is directly related to
their ability to do their jobs. This
segmentation of the work force is used by capital to intensify and solidify
exploitation. Examples abound: the systematic paying of lower wages to women
in comparable jobs; the collaboration in
the nineteenth and early twentieth century between white workers and employers
to exclude black workers from industrial jobs, which gave the white workers
protection from competition by black workers and enabled employers to pay those
white workers lower wages; the
elaborately hierarchical system of education credentials that effectively
excludes large segments of the working class from access to less physical wearing
and better paying jobs. And, perhaps
most important of all, advances in transportation, shipping, and the scheduling
of supplies for production that makes possible systematic outsourcing of jobs
to any area of the world in which wages are low.
All of this raises a question that could not easily or
naturally be posed within the theoretical confines of Marx's analysis of
capitalism, viz, Does it make sense
to speak of some well-paid employees in a corporate hierarchy as being both
exploited by the owners of capital and also exploiters of those below them in
the wage hierarchy? In short, can we
make sense of the notion of relative
exploitation?
One way to think of relative exploitation is as an extension
of Marx's claim that a variety of social or economic fragments -- land-owners,
financiers, middlemen, bankers -- receive transfers of the surplus-labor
extracted from the workers in the production process and realized as
surplus-value in the market. If profit
is the monetary manifestation of this surplus value, and if some portion of
that profit ends up in the pockets of persons who are not themselves owners of
capital, then perhaps some of the high wages paid to corporate executives [not
to speak of university professors] should be understood not as the cost of
reproducing their labor-power but as a share of the surplus value extracted
from less well-paid workers.
Does this mean that those in the middle or upper reaches of
the wage hierarchy are not exploited, but are only exploiters, like the
capitalists? No, some modern Marxian
analysts argue. There is a structure of
relative exploitation, more complex than Marx imagined, within which some
individuals are only exploited [low wage workers], some individuals are both
exploited and exploiters [high wage workers whose wages are secured and
protected by the segmentation of the labor force,] and some individuals are
exploiters only [owners of capital or those whom effectively control capital
and use that control to direct some portion of the profits into their pockets.]
A
classic analysis of this idea of relative exploitation, by my old friends and
UMass colleagues Sam Bowles and Herb Gintis, can be found in their 1977 article
"The
Marxian Theory of Value
and Heterogeneous Labour: A Critique and Reformulation", Cambridge
Journal of Economics, Vol. 1(2), pp. 173-192. [A warning.
The math is somewhat formidable for us novices.]
I shall try to find time to go into this in my course next semester.
9 comments:
This argument falls under the view that exploitation is somehow theft, and theft is wrong, correct?
do you mean "falls" as in "fails," or "falls" as in "is classified as"?
The latter. The view that exploitation is theft from the producer, and in this case also some kind of underclass.
I'm just trying to make sense of the argument, because I've had a hunch for a few years that theories of exploitation that see exploitation as a form of thievery are going to run into trouble.
This is related to the notion of Uneven Development (Neil Smith? is that the name?).
Your phrase, "some individuals are both exploited and exploiters," seems troublesome to me, in many cases, given that the concept "exploiters" suggest an active, if not, conscious role. Might "passive exploitation" or "passive beneficiary of exploitation" (depending on the circumstances) be more appropriate than "relative exploitation?" I'm thinking of white semi-killed workers who are exploited, have a tough time making ends meet, and who are clueless about any of this.
Jerry, exploitation cannot involve a conscious role, under Marx's terms, since the majority of capitalists are not conscious of the fact that surplus value comes from production, and unnecessary labor time. As Marx shows, they think their surplus value comes from thrift, selling dear, and overall cunning, they are often overlooking the fact that it comes from the working class.
Thanks Chris. Yet the question of responsibility remains. Is the exploited semi-skilled worker who merely shows up for work each day, often risking his or her life in the process, and who is inserted into a segmented labor force and who makes no decisions but is directed daily, responsible for the exploitation below to the degree that he or she can be labled an "exploiter?"
I think I need to read the paper Wolff cites, the whole concept of relative exploitation seems oddly dubious, since exploitation is a class relationship around who owns the means of production....
Except, Chris, that at least for some Marxian traditions, ownership of means of production is incidental to, or at least less important than, the question of who produces and who appropriates the surplus.
Post a Comment