A few brief words of explanation before I continue my
reflections. First of all, you must not
make the mistake of thinking that I cannot be correct in attributing some feature
or characteristic or arrangement to socialism simply because you can cite examples
of that feature or characteristic or arrangement in some existing capitalist economy. Of course that will often be true! If socialism is going to grow in the womb of
capitalism, as Marx puts it, then we will find many examples of just such
anticipations. For example, to refer
once again to my essay “The Future of Socialism,” we will find in capitalist
corporations the development of decision-making that is guided by
considerations that are essentially political rather than market-driven in
their formal structure. It will
certainly not be the case that all
decisions are entirely market-driven until the moment when capitalism is
replaced by socialism, at which point decisions will abruptly start to be
political in their logical structure.
That is just what Marx, with brilliant insight, taught us not to expect.
Yesterday, I wrote about overcoming certain elements of work
alienation by integrating the decision-making and planning elements of the
production process with the various stages of the carrying out of that process,
so that workers who spend some of their time doing boring or repetitive or even
distasteful things will accept those as part of a larger process they have
helped to design and shape. Of course we
would expect to find examples of just this sort of integration of the
production process within capitalist economies.
How could it be otherwise? I hope
this point is clear, and will be kept in mind as I continue with my
reflections.
Second, I try very hard to talk about this subject without
using the jargon that has grown up in Marxian circles over the past century and
a half. I believe very strongly that if
what I am saying makes sense, then it ought to be possible for me to say it in
plain English, with as many concrete examples as possible, and without the
slightest whiff of sectarianism of the sort so common in both religious and
economic debates. I have all my life
been convinced that that is the right way to think and talk about these
matters, and I shall not allow myself to be drawn into the ritual citation of
proof texts from the Sacred Writings.
Today I want to say a few words about how the distribution
of the social product will differ under socialism. The total social output of goods and services
in an advanced capitalist economy is the collective product of all the hundreds
of millions of men, women, and yes children who together constitute the labor
force of the society, whether that labor force receives wages and salaries or
not. Men or women making dinner in a
household are contributing to that output, as are children looking after their
younger brothers and sisters. We can
talk another time about the complex technical problem of designing measures of
the social output that capture all such efforts, but I think we can agree that
they must be included in our thinking and calculations.
Some of what is produced in any cycle of production must be
set aside as input into the next cycle of production. I don’t care a great deal whether we call
this “capital” or refuse to use that term because it is somehow peculiar to the
capitalist mode of production, but call it what you will, if we do not set it
aside [if we eat our seed corn], then the society will very quickly go to hell in
a handbasket. Furthermore, since tools
and machines and buildings wear out, we must set aside an appropriate amount,
in some form or other, as a depreciation fund, so that the tools, machines, and
buildings can be replaced.
The society must also decide, collectively, whether it
wishes to expand the scope of production – in short, the society must decide on
an appropriate rate of growth. If the
population is growing, a rate of growth equal to the growth of the population
will be required in order to maintain the existing standard of living. In addition, changes in the demography of the
population [a larger percentage of people past the age when they are called on
to work productively, for example] will require corresponding changes in the
productivity of those actually engaged in productive labor. Collective decisions about the length of the
work day, work week, and work year will also shape the decisions about growth
and productivity.
In a capitalist economy, everything else is divided into
wages and privately appropriated profits, but in a socialist economy, the
portion now appropriated by capital as profit will be part of the wages fund. That leaves undetermined how the wages fund
will be divided up among the entire population [those who are engaged in
productive labor and those who, for whatever reason, are not.] In short, how equal or unequal will wages be
under socialism?
There are two well-known theoretical arguments designed to
show that a simple equalization of the distribution of the social product would
be so inefficient as to be irrational and indefensible. The first is the theory that wages in a
market-driven economy will equal the marginal product of the worker being
paid. I have had my say about this
argument elsewhere, and will not deal with it again here.
The second is the theory that jobs requiring special
training, skills, or effort will have to be paid a wage premium in order to
encourage the ablest, best-suited candidates to offer themselves for
employment. Society needs those with the
most talent for brain surgery to undergo the lengthy and rigorous training required
to prepare someone to cut open heads and mess with brains. The same is true for airline pilots,
cellphone designers, philosophy professors, and the managers of large
productive enterprises. Since the jobs
are demanding and the preparation arduous, those with the requisite talents
need to be motivated by higher than average wages to pursue such careers. If this process of recruitment and selection
is successful, the total social product will be so much enlarged over what would
result from random job assignments that there will actually be a good deal more
in the way of goods and services to spread around and benefit everyone, even
after the wage supplements have been paid.
This, as I am sure you all know, is the central thesis of John Rawls’
famous and influential book, A Theory of
Justice. Rawls, by the way, says that
only as much in the way of a wage supplement is justified as is required to
attract the especially talented. Not
many readers, it is my impression, think very deeply about how profoundly
radical this seemingly benign claim is [I am not entirely sure Rawls understood
that himself, although he was very smart, so perhaps he did.]
I have always found Rawls’ argument rather odd, I must
confess [the same argument, by the way, shows up in one form or another in a very
great many serious works of economics and sociology.] If I may caricature the argument in a
mean-spirited, but not really unfair, manner, it amounts to this:
Why should we pay philosophy professors considerably more
than garbage collectors? Because it takes
a very special talent and a great deal of work to prepare oneself to be a good
philosophy professor. Now, all of us
would rather spend our lives collecting garbage than writing philosophy and teaching
philosophy to young men and women. Or at
the very least, all of us are indifferent between spending our lives collecting
garbage and spending our lives writing philosophy and teaching it to young men
and women. But if we simply allot the
preferred jobs of garbage collector by lot, leaving the unlucky losers to teach
philosophy, we will get some very indifferent philosophy, to the general detriment
of society. So some way must be found to
induce those with a gift for philosophy to turn away from their first choice –
garbage collection – and agree to go to graduate school. Hence the wage premium attached to the
professorships of philosophy. These
things are very difficult to titrate precisely, but if we arrange the wage
premiums with care, the happiness and general job satisfaction of the garbage
collectors will just about be matched by the lesser happiness and job
satisfaction of the philosophy professors, as then topped up by what they can
buy with their wage supplements.
I realize that this sounds bizarre, but it is really what
Rawls’ theory implies, if you think about it.
On the other hand, if you think, as I am inclined to, that those with a
talent for philosophy really would very much prefer to spend their lives as professors
of philosophy, then Rawls’ theory implies that they ought to be willing to pay
for the privilege by taking a lower wage than that paid to garbage collectors
or factory operatives or the women who make the beds and clean the rooms in
hotels. If that strikes you as absurd,
you might want to try to spell out exactly why.
4 comments:
Thanks for starting this great discussion. I have many thoughts on your theme “What would socialism look like?”. But first I’d like to address your discussion of Rawls.
As I have always understood Rawls, his principle on income inequality and incentives was both more general and more specific than the one that you set out in your post: i.e., that we should tolerate income inequality only to the extent that it provides an incentive for those with the necessary talent to undertake arduous training for socially beneficial and desirable professions. “More general” in that Rawls said that we should tolerate income inequality in ANY case where it provides incentives for people to undertake socially necessary tasks that would not otherwise take place—such that garbage collectors may make more than philosophy professors. “More specific” in that he said that income inequality was only justifiable to the extent that it made the LEAST well off in society better off. (This last point is very important. ) If this is not Rawls, and only something I dreamt up myself, then I will happily take credit for it! I think that it is the only defensible justification for inequality. (Jerry Cohen has mounted the only even partially convincing attack that I have seen.) The implications of this simply-stated principle are profound, far-reaching, and, as you point out, extremely radical—particularly in “my” version of it. It is also worth noting that there is nothing in the principle that is at odds with the principles of neoclassical economics. (But that’s for another comment.)
Now I’d like to comment on an interesting question that you raise, and tentatively answer, in your previous post: “could factory or office work in a socialist economy be, if not thrilling or life-affirming, at least a good deal less alienated than it is now? Perhaps so, if those doing the work play a significant role – not a merely symbolic role – in the planning, designing, and overseeing of the work they are doing, and if ways are found to vary the tasks they perform.”
I am pessimistic about this solution to the problem of alienation for two reasons.
First, I think that it is at odds with the division of labour, specialisation and automation—in short, the labour productivity--that has created the material preconditions for us to raise, without sounding absurd, the question “What would socialism look like?” at all. I agree with you that we should not take Marx’s lines about hunting, fishing and criticising too seriously. I think that what he says elsewhere, and most eloquently in the Manifesto, is both more realistic and more consistent with what he believed. Newcomers to Marx are sometimes surprised at what sounds like Chamber of Commerce “boosterism” in the Manifesto, when Marx waxes eloquent about the many positive changes that Capitalism has wrought, not the least of which is creating the material pre-conditions for a socialist future. But it is indeed the massive increase in the goods and services produced per hour of work that has made any talk of socialism possible. And it is hard, for me at least, to see how we can have the MRI machine you refer to without the specialisation and alienating forms of work that you describe. (As an aside, this is to me one of the contradictions of Marxism, or at least of the kind of Marxism that Chris has espoused on this blog.) And never mind the MRI. As someone else I read once pointed out, just imagine all of the information flows, decisions and processes--and the many, many individuals that played some role in each--that it takes to get the lowly, foil-wrapped pat of butter from the cow onto your tray in an airline flight.
Second, I am not sure that everyone would even want to participate in the “planning, designing, and overseeing of the work that they are doing.” I know that I don’t. I am close to the end of a career in the business world where I have held senior positions, but never been the ultimate boss. I have had my share of decisions that didn’t go my way. But I would much rather see a decision made and move on than get bogged down in endless debate and complex voting schemes. For me, the Occupy Wall Street form of democracy is a vision of hell. I’ll qualify this by saying that I’m not talking about decisions to do anything illegal. And I certainly don’t appreciate commands from on high with no debate of any kind. I just mean that, in my experience, once the various alternatives and their pros and cons have been aired, it is better that someone breaks the tie and we move on, provided of course that the person who has final say is also accountable for the consequences. I have often been surprised later at the number of times that what seemed like momentous decisions in the end didn’t matter much one way or the other. Such is the human mess! I’d be curious if the experience is similar in the academic world.
So, what to do? I think that the solution is to simply accept that many jobs will be boring and but aim to reduce the amount of labour as much as possible—shorter days, shorter weeks, combined with various mechanisms of income redistribution, based on some kind of Rawlsian principle.
How has the "Marxism" I've "espoused" been in contradiction to the production of an MRI machine?
The GI (1845-6) and CM (1848) were both co-authored by Engels, who ghost wrote some of Marx's journalism pieces as well, to help earn Marx extra money. Unfortunately, almost everything of intellectual importance is attributed to Marx rather than both of them. This is especially true of academic and Ph.D holding individuals with revolutionary pretensions who tend to identify with Marx rather than Engels who was, I might add, quite the humble man. It must be remembered that the arguments found in Socialism: Utopian and Scientific had quite an impact in bringing people to communism. Engels also went out of his way to consolidate Marx's influence among competing revolutionary programs in a number of works, including Anti-Duhring and Revolution in Science which defended Marx's commanding position among radicals back then. In short, Engels gave and contributed too, especially when it came to money which he knew how to make, save, and give away.
Post a Comment