A. Wilmsen’s Critique of Lee
Wilmsen’s
critique operates at a number of different levels. The broadest or most
encompassing level is his invocation and adaptation of the notion of world
systems advanced by Immanuel Wallerstein and others, mostly in the context of
debates about Third World underdevelopment. There had been a tendency among
economists and historians, and of course very much more markedly among
anthropologists, to conceive third world nations or regions [and, within
anthropology, primitive peoples] as autarchic - as isolated, self-sufficient
social systems whose principal characteristics could be, indeed had to be,
explained by appeal to internal features. The interactions of these
independent systems with advanced industrial capitalist nations [I am
deliberately using the language in which these theses were advanced - you must
read my discourse ironically] were understood as secondary, externally imposed
deformations, rather than as partially constitutive of the societies
themselves. Wallerstein et al. argued, in effect, that it was no more
reasonable to construe Latin America or Southeast Asia or Africa in this way
than it would be to construe the working class of a capitalist economy and
society as an independent social formation defined and determined independently
of its relation to the capitalist class. Instead, they said, we must understand
the entire world economy as a single system, in which, for example, the
depressing of the prices of primary products relative to manufactured goods on
the world market plays the same role as the depressing of wages within a market
economy, and so forth.
Anthropologists
have typically understood "their tribes" as isolated, complete social
units, at most standing in some on-going interaction with other tribes in the
vicinity. Adapting Wallerstein, Wilmsen argues that the Zhu can only be
properly understood as thoroughly integrated into a larger economic system
encompassing not only the rest of Southern Africa, but also Europe, Asia,
Northern Africa, and the Western Hemisphere. They must be seen both as
occupying a class position in that larger system, and as exhibiting an
internal class structure based upon differential access to and control of land
and water. If Wilmsen can make this case, then he has effectively refuted the
theoretical classification of the Zhu as pre-historic hunter-gatherers.
In
support of his counter-claim, Wilmsen presents three bodies of detailed
evidence:
1. Historical materials drawn
from government archives in Botswana and other sources dealing with the events
of the past two to three centuries in Southern Africa. From these materials,
Wilmsen draws three lessons. First, the region of the Kalahari in which the Zhu
are found is not an Outback or backwater, but has historically been
intersected by trade routes linking the Kalahari with the Indian and Atlantic
Oceans and beyond. Second, the Zhu were in relatively recent times herders of
cattle and farmers, so that it is unjustified to construe their present
foraging as the continuation, unbroken, of pre-historic modes of survival. And
Third, the Zhu who now live in the Kalahari and were the objects of Lee's
investigations are in fact an underclass who have, within the past century and
a bit more, been driven off their cattle posts and lands, deprived of their
lucrative trade activities, and consigned to a meagre, marginal existence at the
bottom of the class hierarchy. In effect - this is my analogy, not Wilmsen's -
it is as though Lee were to come to New York, observe homeless men and women
living on the streets and grubbing in garbage cans, and were to fail to notice
that they are the underclass of a capitalist economy, construing them instead
as traditional hunter-gatherers. [This analogy is a bit harsh, of course]
2. Archeological materials
drawn from his and other people's digs, showing that cattle herding, farming,
and large-scale trade had flourished in the Kalahari for at least two thousand
years. Wilmsen is able to draw some rather elegant inferences, from such
unlikely data as statistical counts of animal bones, concerning the existence
of an elaborate class structure at an earlier time.
3. Direct observation and
interpretation of present-day Zhu, designed to demonstrate, among other things:
First, that the Zhu do in fact have a clearly defined class structure [and
hence, you see, a history - that is the point of proving this], based
principally upon property rights in available water sources, so that it is incorrect
to understand their various practices, such as the nomadic movement from
water hole to water hole, purely as a species adaptation to the environment,
unmediated by differential class interests;[1]
and Second, that for the Zhu, kinship relations are not a mechanically enacted
system of rigid rules, but are a flexible structure within which individuals
find political advantages and disadvantages, for example by interpreting
kinship relations so as to favor or disfavor marriages that will in turn
advance or frustrate their economic interests.
This
last point is rather subtle, and in my opinion very important. European
historians, for example of eighteenth century England [such as Lewis Namier],
have taught us to understand extended family relationships, especially of those
in the ruling circles, as matrices within which individuals pursue political
ends by manipulating kinship ties in flexible ways. One need merely consult the
novels of Jane Austen to see how this was done in practice.
Anthropological
accounts of kinship relations subtly shift the explanatory balance,
representing the structural relationships as primary and the participants in
them as secondary instantiations of them.
The
effect, both literary and theoretical, is to represent the upper classes of
England as having a politics, but to deny that the people of "primitive
tribes" do. In this way, the Zhu are figured as not like us -
perhaps superior, perhaps inferior, but inescapably other. Wilmsen's
analyses of property relations as mediated by kinship seek to alter this
conception.
Once
again, an example drawn from popular entertainment may make the point more
successfully than an abstract characterization. Everyone who has spent much
time, as I have, watching westerns and explorer movies like King Solomon's
Mines grows accustomed to Red Indians and African savages who speak an odd
pigeon English even when they are supposedly speaking to one another in
their native tongue! "White man speak with forked tongue, Little
Bear." "Yes, Running Fox, but great chief wise, find truth in white
man's words." That sort of thing. Now, when you think about it, every
human being is a native speaker of some language, and in your own
linguistic community, what you say and what is said to you sounds, to your ear,
perfectly normal and without accent. It is only out siders and foreigners who
talk funny. The popular representations of "primitive" peoples
portray them, by this simple linguistic device, as inherently simple-minded.
This elementary fact was brought home to me some while ago by watching a
television production in the United States of a several-part history of Shaka,
the Zulu king. Far and away the most extraordinary feature of the production
was the fact that Shaka and his principal minister engaged in perfectly
grammatical, rather sophisticated discussions of political strategy, much as
two characters in one of Shakespeare's history plays might have. The effect on
the audience, I can testify, was to make Shaka and his minister seem like
effective, intelligent politicians, which is presumably what they were.
Wilmsen
makes very much the same point directly, in reporting several conversations
with a man named Halengisi. Here are the passages, taken from pages 251 and
268:
Halengisi insists that the past was better than the
present - he once said to me, with a wave of his hand at the herds around us,
"Gumisi ka kwarra kwinki": ''There are no cattle here now." He
made this remark while we were standing together near the CaeCae wells
surrounded by about a third of the more than six hundred cattle kept here; we
were, in fact, leaning against his magnificent bull, in which he took
justifiable pride. He was of course speaking rhetorically and went on to say
that in recent years his homestead had suffered substantial losses due to the
poisonous plant mai. [251]
Lee relates conversations with two Kaos at Dobe who
appear to suggest that Zhu ridicule the notion of Zhu headmen. In fact, many do
so. But they do so with irony ... Just as with Halengisi's rhetorical dismissal
of the cattle standing around him, it is mistaken to take these anecdotes at
face value. [268]
I would suggest that the
ability to recognize ironic communication from someone is a very important mark
of one's conceptualization of that person as like oneself.
Finally,
there is the most astonishing argument in the entire book, namely Wilmsen's
claim that Lee et al. have not even been able to describe the gross physical characteristics
of the Zhu correctly! Wilmsen actually argues that they are not genetically
small; they are just hungry! I hope you can appreciate just how insulting this
is to Lee. It is as though a revisionist historian were to say to one of the
most prominent students of medieval Europe, “Did you perhaps fail to notice
that the documents on which you base your research were written in Latin, and
not English as you appear to have thought?" It is scarcely any wonder that
Lee has not been amused.
Although
Wilmsen's critique focuses in detail on the techniques and conclusions of Lee's
research, the remark quoted earlier about the end of ethnography makes it clear
that his real target is the fundamental presupposition underlying all such
anthropological work, no matter how well carried out. Wilmsen seeks to call
into question the very existence of the object that ethnography studies, namely
culture. Everything in the critique turns on this point, so we must try
to get as clear as we can about the concept of culture in its ethnographic
usages.
1.
The
Ethnographic Concept of Culture
The
term "culture," like its cognates in other European languages is, as
Raymond Williams notes, extremely complex and problematical, with root meanings
both of tending crops and of honoring through religious ceremonies. The former
sense gives rise to the familiar notion of culture, or cultivation, as a
special development of talents and sensibilities, particularly in relation to
aesthetic productions, as when we speak of a person as cultivated, or of the
high culture of a civilization. The clear implication is that culture is
something the upper classes have, the middle classes aspire to, and the lower
classes lack.
These
meanings play a familiar role in seventeenth and eighteenth century satires of
bourgeois pretensions and social climbing. The upper classes need not acquire
culture; they have it [like the upper crust Boston lady, who, when asked by an
arriviste where she bought her hats, replied, "We do not buy our
hats; we have our hats."] The middle classes, born without culture,
desperately seek to acquire it, through dancing schools, grand tours of the
continent, and lavish endowments of ballet or opera, all in a comic, but of course ultimately unsuccessful,
effort to pass as upper class. The working class is too coarse even to acquire
the patina of culture. At best, they have folkways, which are a natural subject
for humor.
A
sophisticated observer will be able to tell at a glance whether someone is
truly cultivated or a mere imposter. [This conception, after undergoing a
variety of transformations, resurfaces in the odd Victorian literary conceit
that an Englishman can pass himself off as Indian or Arab merely by darkening
his skin, donning the appropriate clothes, and studying the local dialects,
whereas a member of a lower order, such as an Indian, will make himself into a
buffoon should he attempt to acquire English culture. See Kipling's Kim, for
example. The apotheosis of this nutty notion can be found in Edgar Rice
Burroughs' Tarzan of the Apes, in which a titled English nobleman, Lord
Greystoke, orphaned in Africa as a baby and raised by apes, teaches himself how
to speak English by looking at a primer left by his dead parents!
Apparently not only courage, nobility, and refinement, but even spoken English,
are encoded in the genetic materials of the English upper classes.]
In
the nineteenth century, the aristocratic notion of culture undergoes a
transformation that is both democratic and scientific. Rather like Moliere's bourgeois
gentilhomme, M. Jourdain, who discovered that he had been speaking prose
all his life, anthropologists discovered that not merely the upper classes, but
every human group, possessed a culture. And this culture could become
the object of systematic, scientific investigation. The new understanding of
the concept received its first and most influential articulation in a classic
early work by E. B. Tylor, entitled Primitive Culture.
Culture or Civilization, taken in its wide ethnographic
sense, is that complex whole that includes knowledge, belief, art, morals, law,
custom, and any other capabilities acquired by man as a member of society. The
condition of culture among the various societies of mankind, in so far as it is
capable of being investigated on general principles, is a subject apt for the
study of laws of human thought and action.
We
find here the core idea on which modern ethnography is based: Each human
group-tribe, clan, nation, society, civilization - has or exhibits a culture
that defines its social nature and makes its members what they are: Medes,
Persians, Ashanti, Iroquois, French, Chinese, Yoruba, or Zhu. To understand a
people is thus to form an adequate concept of its culture. To know the
Trobriand Islanders is to have a coherent, complete, abstract idea of Trobriand
culture - not a tasteful appreciation of Trobriand Island food, wine, and
music, but an organized insight into the collectively shared and reproduced
forms of life that make the Trobriand Islanders what they are.
This
truly is an instance of that much over-worked term of analysis and opprobrium,
"essentialism." Culture, as ethnographers understand it, is not a
mere aggregation of traits, practices, verbal behaviors, beliefs, and institutions,
identified piecemeal by careful observation and recorded in open-ended lists. The culture of a people is
construed by anthropologists as a stable, organically interrelated, homeostatic
whole in which individuals more or less fully participate, and in virtue of
which participation they can properly be identified as Ashanti,
Trobriand, or Zhu. The several components of a culture are connected with one
another in such a fashion that to understand one requires understanding the whole.
Disturb one component - by introducing foreign influences through the very
presence of the ethnographer, for example - and the whole will strive to
readjust and reassert itself so as to preserve its coherent unity.
The
culture of a people, thus conceived by ethnography, is a collective human
product, stable over time and shared more or less fully by all the members of
the society. Like Durkheim's "collective unconscious," the culture of
a people is an independent object of investigation, expressed in the
behavior of the members of the society but not consisting merely of the
aggregative sum of those behaviors.
Like
all appeals to essential form, this concept of culture is implicitly
evaluative. To say that it is part of the culture of Germans to conform rigidly
to bureaucratic regulations is, unavoidably, to say that someone careless of
rules cannot be a true German. To say that the Zhu share their meat with the
entire circle of persons in their band is to say that a Zhu who refuses to
share, as a consequence, perhaps, of a stay in the South African army is losing
his Zhu-ishness, ceasing to be truly Zhu. It is then a very small step to the
conclusion that we, as anthropologists, should do whatever we can to preserve
the Zhu way of life, even over the objections of the individual himself, who
may prefer not to continue to share his meat.
Many
of you are familiar with one variant of this conception of culture as an
essential form. I am speaking, of course, of the theory of intuited cultural
unities that underlies Fundamental Pedagogics. In that version, the notion of
culture finds its way into the theory of Christian National Education on which
the Bantu educational system is grounded, as well as into the official
rationale for Apartheid. This South African incarnation of the theory can be
traced to twentieth century Dutch philosophers who were themselves influenced
by Edmund Husserl's theories of phenomenology.
What
is implicit in ethnography is made explicit in Fundamental Pedagogics, namely
that human beings can be understood to be divided into discrete groups (nations,
or tribes, or peoples), each of which instantiates an essential cultural form
whose inner coherence, unity, and independence is a matter of objective fact,
cognizable by a rational intuition or grasping of essences. A core element of
this essential form is a common language, which, as the bearer of the folkways,
customs, and peculiar genius of the people, must be preserved if the essence is
to be preserved.
You
are all familiar with the political conclusions drawn from this theory by
academic and state defenders of the system of Apartheid. I shall return to that
subject near the end of my remarks. But it may perhaps not have occurred to you
consciously that the discipline of ethnography rests on the same premises about
the existence of cultural forms as does the theory of Apartheid. What is more,
you may have overlooked the fact that in contemporary discussions on the left
about cultural oppression, cultural resistance, cultural liberation,
multi-culturalism, and the role of culture in the struggle against tyranny,
very much the same concept of culture is at work. I am shamelessly
playing on your aversion to Apartheid and to its rationale in the theory of
Fundamental Pedagogics as a way of getting you to rethink the apparently
politically acceptable version of the concept of culture.
In
addition to providing the object of inquiry that legitimates ethnography as an
autonomous discipline, the notion of an essential cultural form also solves
certain very practical problems of research that troubled ethnographers in the
early part of this century. The problems are obvious enough: The researcher is
working with an unfamiliar language for which there are neither dictionaries
nor written texts, and whose syntax may be dramatically unlike that of any
language he or she already knows; the ethnographer brings along a great deal of
conceptual baggage to the field, and may suffer the same ethnocentric blindness
that had so obviously afflicted missionaries, explorers, and other precursors;
and even as lengthy a field trip as two years hardly seems enough to become
intimately familiar with a people whose customs and social relationships bear
very little resemblance to those of the ethnographer. These problems threatened
to invalidate the work of the early ethnographers, to reduce their accounts to
nothing more than interesting anecdotes about mostly naked people.
The
concept of culture, suitably elaborated, provided the solution. In a
widely-read essay entitled "On Ethnographic Authority," James
Clifford has summarized the assumptions that rationalized the practices of
ethnographic field-workers.
In the 1920's the new fieldworker-theorist brought to
completion a powerful new scientific and literary genre, the ethnography, a
synthetic cultural description based on participant observation. The new style
of representation depended on institutional and methodological innovations
circumventing the obstacles to rapid knowledge of other cultures that had
preoccupied the best representatives of [R.H.] Codrington's generation
[the late nineteenth century.]
Clifford
identifies six innovations of the new ethnography. Note, by the way, that his
primary interest is in the implications of these innovations for the literary
form of ethnographic writing - not the focus of my remarks.
1. ''The persona of the fieldworker was validated" as
professional, heroic, scientifically trained, and possessed of a suitably
non-colonial cultural relativism;
2. "[I]t was tacitly agreed that the new-style
ethnographer, whose sojourn in the field seldom exceeded two years, and
frequently was much shorter, could efficiently 'use' native languages without
'mastering' them;"
3. ''The new ethnography was marked by an increased emphasis on
the power of observation;"
4. A general theoretical understanding of culture would permit
the trained ethnographer to get to the heart of a culture without a time-consuming
inventory of native customs and a thorough mastery of the local language;
5. The conception of culture as an organic unity made it
possible to study the whole through a suitably insightful understanding of a
single part, such as a religious rite, a gift-giving practice, or the life
cycle of a single individual; and
6. ''The wholes thus represented tended to be synchronic,
products of short-term research activity."
It
would be too easy to construe these assumptions as the self-serving
rationalizations of anthropologists caught between the constraints of their
undertaking and the genuine prerequisites of a successful ethnography.
Philosophers like myself, for whom research consists of consulting several of
the books on my shelves, find it hard to appreciate the commitment of time,
energy, and inner personal resources required to live for several years in a
thoroughly unfamiliar physical and social environment, to learn from scratch,
without primers or dictionaries, a language bearing no recognizable
relationship to one's own, to eat strange food, and witness or participate in
alien rituals, all the while attempting to grasp in a coherent, organized
manner the folkways and lifeways of a culturally distant people. Any man or
woman who actually makes that effort and commits that time cannot help but
believe that it constitutes an adequate basis for some sort of scientifically
legitimate account.
Put
baldly, Clifford's second assumption, about the usability of limited language
skills, seems transparently self-serving. But imagine having actually spent
that two years "in the bush," able finally to speak to the Zhu, the
Trobriand Islanders, the Nuer, however haltingly! Imagine, as well, that you
are writing for an audience that has never even heard of the Nuer or Zhu before
you present them with your results. Wouldn't any of us believe that even a
limited linguistic competence gave us some access to the culture of "our tribe,"
particularly when supplemented by a theoretical framework extracted from a
wide-ranging cross-cultural survey of the folkways of dozens of peoples from
every corner of the globe?
The
exotic character of most ethnographic fieldwork, I suggest, gets in the way of
our thinking intelligently about the theoretical presuppositions on which it is
based. As I read, for example, I fleetingly form certain of the words in the
text sublingually with the muscles that would be activated were I reading
aloud. When I read Lee's or Wilmsen's account of the Zhu, I find my throat
constricting from the unsuccessful effort to make the click sounds represented
in the text by a variety of exclamation marks, backslashes, and implausibly
placed consonants. That physical reaction, always lurking at the edge of my
awareness when I read about the Zhu, is
enough to guarantee that I will experience any account of them as alien,
exotic, and hence impervious to certain sorts of theoretical critiques. I
cannot help but believe that someone who has mastered the language of the Zhu
must understand what they are really like.
I
wish to persuade you [following Wilmsen] that the entire ethnographic
enterprise is fundamentally misguided. The attempt to grasp the cultural
essence of a people must fail, not because their language is too difficult, or
because their folkways are too different from our own, or because even the most
extended field trip is too short a time to accomplish so difficult a task, but
because there is no cultural essence to be grasped. As Gertrude
Stein is reputed to have said about Oakland, California after encountering its
utter lack of urban distinction, ''There is no there there."
The
difficulties of unmanageable languages and unfamiliar customs merely distract
us from focusing on the real issue, which is whether it is possible to
identify, by whatever combination of observation, experiment, and theoretical
interpretation, the culture of a people. Lee might have asked himself
how a knowledgeable and thoughtful Zhu understands his or her own society, but
that would just have compounded the problem, for then he would have had to
decide who in a Zhu community fits this description and try, with his uncertain
language skills, to understand the account he or she gives. What is more, Lee
can never successfully bracket the plain fact that he has arrived from over the
horizon in a Land Rover, distributed trinkets, pots, and canned food to win his
way into the community, and offered payment in return for the spontaneous
ruminations of his chosen informants.
I
might seek to circumvent the practical difficulties of ethnographic research by
turning my attention to the culture of my own society. I speak the
language like a native - indeed, as a native; I have fifty-eight years
of on-site experience; I am as familiar with the rituals, practices, body
language, and nuances as a lifetime can make me; and I do not generate
unintended consequences as a participant observer that might distort my
observations.
There
are, of course, many literary precedents for such an undertaking. At their best
they can be amusing and suggestive. But as soon as one asks whether such
literary productions really capture what it is to be an American, one
realizes that there is something badly wrong with the question. One can write
about the economic, political, or religious activities of Americans; one can
inquire into the varieties, and trajectories of change, of American families;
one can analyze the structure of an American institution, such as the national
army, or the two-year Community College, or the large eleemosynary foundation.
But such inquiries do not answer the question that ethnographers seem bent upon
investigating, namely, what is the essence of American culture.
What
are the boundaries of the object to be investigated. Am I seeking the essence,
the cultural form, of Western Civilization, Anglo-American Civilization, North
American Civilization, the civilization of the United States, late twentieth
century northeastern United States upper middle class urban assimilated Jewish
intellectual civilization, or perhaps merely the culture of the Wolff family?
No doubt, to a North American anthropologist, all Zhu look alike, but if a Zhu
is anything at all like a Jew, then you can be certain that Zhu perceive profound
differences, indeed chasms, among themselves that an ethnographer will ignore
only at great methodological peril.
Nor
can one fall back on the fact that all of the people at the !Dobe water hole
speak the same language. The same thing is true of the patrons of a singles bar
on the upper East Side of New York City, but it would be a naive student of
North American ethnography who would infer the cultural unity of that watering
hole.
The
central problem here, I think, is that the notion of a cultural essence, looked
at one way, is manifestly absurd and rather ominous. But the same notion,
looked at slightly differently, seems quite reasonable, usable, and
unthreatening. It is time, therefore, for me to attempt some more systematic
analysis of the concept of culture, in an effort to identify which elements in
it have a legitimate grounding, and which are false and misleading. What
follows is unavoidably theoretical, but I hope this very lengthy prelude has
sufficiently engaged your interest to sustain all of us through what may be a
rather dry patch.
[1] A number of quite practical debates,
even court cases, have occurred in Australia, Botswana, and elsewhere
concerning this issue of property rights. Briefly, what happens is that a
colonial power moves in and lays claim to certain property [typically, to land],
ignoring the rights of the indigenous peoples. Complaints are brought by them,
or. in their name, in the law courts of the colonial power, and the question is
raised whether the indigenous peoples have a system of property that is
recognizable by the colonial legal code - there being, usually, some provision
in the colonial law for acknowledging property claims made in systems of law
other than itself. At this point, it becomes a matter of very considerable
moment whether what we recognize as property rights are part of the culture of
the indigenous peoples. Anthropologists from the colonial power's society step
in to argue for the rights of the indigenous peoples. And so forth. As you will
easily imagine, very tricky and interesting conceptual problems arise
concerning what does and what does not count as an indigenous system of
property rights. Wilmsen has edited a very interesting book entitled We Arc
Herc: Politics of Aboriginal Land Tenure [U. Cal. Press, 1989] that deals
with these questions.
3 comments:
Think of Ruth Benedict's patterns of culture- yes there is no essence, there is a Gestalt.
Your reductio absurdam is absurd
I mean what you are engaging in is an egregious form of armchair anthropology- you are merely privileging your personal intuitions dressed up with fancy language.
And like most philosophers you merely assume you are right rather than prove anything
The fact that there is no essence to a culture does not show that there aren't cultures.
Let's take middle class Chileans. I'd say that they share certain beliefs, prejudices, social practices, manners, habits of consumption, ways of raising their children, etc. (not a complete list of all they have in common), which are different in many respects from those of middle class whites in the U.S.
Do they all follow all of them 100%? Of course not, but I doubt that anyone serious who uses the term "culture" means that they all raise their children in exactly the same way. Maybe Wittgenstein's concept of the family resemblance is more accurate than that of an essence.
So too I imagine that among any African ethnic group there are individual variations in many practices and beliefs but I would imagine that they have many practices and beliefs in common, enough practices and beliefs in common to differentiate them from British aristocrats as a culture.
Post a Comment