A Theoretical Analysis of the Concept of Culture
Let
me begin at a quite general level with some remarks about the formation of
human personality, for it is through the process by which the individual develops
a recognizable personality that what we call culture is transmitted from
generation to generation. Human beings, apparently alone among the animals, are
radically genetically underdetermined. That is to say, the developmental
information carried by the human infant in its genes is thoroughly inadequate
to determine a growth path leading to healthy, functional adulthood.
Rear
a wolf or elephant or shrew or cat in captivity, separated from other members
of its species, and either completely or to a quite considerable extent it will
grow into a recognizably coherent, appropriately graceful, mature instance of
its species. What is more, rear such an animal taken from one population of its
species, and it will, when released, become a functional member of whatever
other population of its species it is placed in. [This claim is a trifle
overstated, for emphasis, and no doubt it fails to take into account some
marvelous traits of dolphins, but the point, nevertheless, is, I believe,
essentially correct.]
Rear
a human infant in isolation from members of its species, on the other hand, and
it does not grow into a recognizably coherent, appropriately graceful,
mature instance of humanity. Instead, what apparently develops is a feral child
incapable of functioning efficiently. Such a creature does not have an
organized, stable personality; it does not interact successfully with its
environment; it lacks entirely that dignity, if I may use an odd term, that
characterizes healthy, mature instances of any animal species.
A
feral child has not been socialized, we say. It lacks language, it
exhibits no style of bodily movements, of the sort that enables us
immediately to distinguish an upper class Englishman from a Japanese warlord, a
Pennsylvania miner from a French boulevardier. One cannot make successful eye
contact with a feral child, it lacks a repertoire of characteristic facial
gestures; in short, it lacks culture. In human beings, but
apparently in no other species, the genetic deficit is made up by a rich, complex,
and almost endlessly variable set of structures that in the individual
constitute personality and in the society as a whole constitute culture. That
is why the shrews or elephants or wolves in one population are, even to very
close observers, much like the shrews, elephants, or wolves in any other
population; and equally, it is why one population of human beings is, in
significant ways, so unlike other populations of humans.[1]
It
is difficult to imagine the evolutionary pathway by which this curious, and
immensely fruitful, genetic underdetermination came about, for it would seem,
speaking rather speculatively, that in its first stages, it would be a
hindrance rather than an aid to reproduction. Quite possibly, it began as a
fortunate by-product of some other more immediately useful variation. But
however it got started, this striking feature of human beings is now firmly
established in our make-up.
Socialization
takes the place of heredity in the transformation of the new-born infant into a
fully developed adult. As the infant interacts with people in its immediate
environment, imitation, identification, and internalization shape the
instinctual energies and primary thought processes into a socialized
personality. The child learns to speak, it learns to control its excretory
processes, it comes to identify itself as gendered - all in whatever fashion it
is taught to do so by its parents or significant others.[2]
When
we easily and unreflectively classify someone as French or Chinese, as an
aristocrat or an arriviste, we are responding to manifold sensory cues that
identify the organization of emotional energies, of large and small muscles, of
habits of behavior and patterns of interaction out of which the individual's
distinctive personality has been formed. As ethnographers have shown us by
generations of imaginative observation and interpretation, these patterns
regulate everything from the political order of the state to the precise way in
which individuals arrange their limbs when they are walking, resting, sleeping,
or eating. The most intimate details of my innermost personality, which I am
prone to cherish [or to despise] as most distinctively myself, are revealed by
suitably trained observers to be routine repetitions of cultural forms
predictably characteristic of my society and utterly foreign to other
societies.
The
meaning-encoded patterns into which the child is socialized, and by the
internalization of which it becomes truly a person, are of course the
collective creations of earlier generations of people. Neither nature nor God
has hard-wired anyone to speak American late-twentieth century English, or to
sit in the definitive fashion of modern Japanese, or to identify mothers'
brothers as the significant men in early life. Each of the elements of our
social life was invented, created, made up, tried out, stumbled upon, by one or
many people.
But
that is not how the elements of culture present themselves to the child. The
child experiences these complex meaningful structures as existing independently
of the self, hence objectively, and as possessing the same natural
inevitability as the properties of physical objects. To most of us, social
roles and structures seem more objective, more necessary, more intractable to
change than even the laws of physical nature. I can more easily imagine a
fictional world in which the law of gravity has been suspended than one in
which there are people who are neither male nor female. All of us experience
social roles and patterns as objectively real structures into which we fit
ourselves, and through adoption of which we define ourselves, even though it
is of course the case that each of them is a human invention, and could have
been constructed quite differently.
What
is more, because these patterns of behavior and feeling are experienced by the
child as objective, they are also experienced as universal rather than
particular. Not only I, but others as well, become who we are by internalizing,
in some form or other, the same repertoire of social forms. When I reflect on
my adult self, and set myself in comparison to others around me, it is natural
for me to perceive all of us as instances of a type, instantiations of a
universal form the nature and existence of which is prior to and hence
independent of any one of us.
Another
personal story, to illustrate this idea. Twenty-five years ago, when I was in a
full-scale Freudian psychoanalysis in New York City, I happened to talk during
one session about Uncle Ben, Aunt Fanny, Cousin Cora and Cousin Tony, my
Italian relatives. My analyst was a rather orthodox Freudian, and hence tended
to say very little, but this was a bit too much even for him. Very quietly and
tentatively, he said, "But I thought you were Jewish." Well, of
course, I am Jewish, but until that moment, I had always thought of Ben,
Fan, Cora, and Tony as Italian. The reasons were simple enough: they were all
overweight, they were very loud, and whenever they arrived at a gathering they
immediately started singing and dancing and playing musical instruments. They
were utterly unlike the rest of my family. Obviously they were Italian! But my
analyst was correct. They really are New York Jews, just like everyone else in
my father's family. If my father, and his older brother and younger sister were
New York Jews, and if Ben grew up in the same household, how could he possibly
be Italian? Being Italian is not like having red hair - something recessive
that crops up from time to time in even the most Jewish of families!
It
would appear, therefore, that the ethnographers are correct in their
supposition that one can understand a people by grasping the essential
structure of its culture, for that essence, though of course not independent of
human existence in general, really is independent of the existence -and nature
of any particular human being. So, if we want to understand Zhu, or Americans,
how can we possibly do better than to identify, describe in suitably general
terms, and exhibit in some theoretical arrangement, the socially transmitted
structures of habit, behavior, and meaning that constitute their culture as
a people?
To
be sure, in carrying out this project, we must be careful to recognize the
enormous variability of culture, the multiplicity of the ways in which that
genetic underdetermination can be filled in by socialization. But ethnographers
need no such caution! Indeed, it is they who have taught us just how various
are the ways that human groups have invented to complete the determination of
personality.
This,
or something like it, is the best case I can think of for the ethnographic
concept of culture as an objectively existing essential form that finds its
instantiation in the practices, institutions, social arrangements, art,
religion, and language of identifiably unified groups of people.
2.
A
Critique of the Concept of Culture
There
is an important element of truth in this account of human personality and
society, but I believe it is fundamentally flawed, in ways that lead, as I
shall suggest shortly, to a reactionary form of ideological obfuscation. The
central inadequacy of this model of personality formation and cultural
transmission is that it construes the individual as the passive recipient of a
socializing process in which certain general forms of behavior, thought, and
feeling are impressed on the partially determined matrix of infantile
mentality. The individual is seen as the bearer of these patterns, a
place-holder who reenacts the meaningful rule-governed scenarios of kinship,
gender, religion, or art that constitute his or her culture. The degree of
integration of the individual personality is thought of as a reflection of the
degree of formal or ideal unity of the ensemble of cultural elements. Thus, a
coherent, well-integrated person, this theory tells us, is a person who fully
and successfully embodies a coherent, well-integrated culture. Inner psychic
disharmony or dysfunctionality is then taken to be a sign of a conflict of
cultures, or the breakdown of cultural unity.
Society,
thus understood, is ahistorical in the sense that the passage of time
bears no essential relationship to the organization of the society. The kinship
relationships, religious rituals, or practices of food production of one
generation are as much, or as little, an expression of the universal cultural
patterns of the society as those of any other generation. Social change, when
it occurs, is either accidental or externally determined, as when changes in
the availability of water or food, natural disasters, or encounters with other
human groups produce internal cultural shifts. And because the passage of time
is, on this understanding, accidental, not essential, the society is conceived
- by ethnographers or others - as having no history. I do not mean simply that
it has no written history. Rather, I mean that the self-understanding of the
people who make up the society is conceived to involve no historical sense of
the internal conflicts, struggles, ambitions, projects, or frustrations of
which genuine human history is composed.
I
think we can now see more clearly the significance of Wilmsen's remarks about Halengisi.
On Wilmsen's account - which strikes me as intrinsically plausible, though I am
obviously quite unqualified to form an independent judgment - Halengisi has an
historical understanding of the relationship between his present situation and
the events of the previous two generations or so. It is that understanding -
indeed, that self-understanding - that allows him to speak ironically,
contrasting the present appearance - which is that he has cattle, since he is
standing in the midst of some and leaning up against one - with the historical reality,
which is that there has been a drastic and devastating decline in the role of
cattle herding in the economy of the Zhu.
The
source of the ahistoricity of the ethnographic conception of culture is its
failure to take account of the purposive character of human action, and the way
in which that purposiveness makes human experience fundamentally historical.
Human beings are intelligently purposive. We live by forming ideas of the way
in which we wish to transform our world, and then acting collectively to
actualize or realize those ideas. That is the central meaning of Marx's famous
early discussion of alienation, which was his word for what happens when this
process goes wrong.
When
we act purposefully, we are oriented forward in time. What is past, because it
cannot be changed, has a significance for us different from the significance of
what is future. Thus, our position in time is asymmetrical. As we live, what
was future, what was the object of our decision and action, what was open to
change, to deliberation, to choice, becomes fixed in the past. At first, we
conceive it as the settled product of our choices, and then, eventually, we
experience it as a part of the unchangeable past - no longer something we did,
but merely something that happened to us.
In
short, the purposive structure of our interaction with the world makes our
lives fundamentally historical.
To
be sure, we conceive our alternatives, project our goals, make our choices,
within a matrix of habits, patterns, and structures of feeling and behavior
that we have internalized as children and experience as objectively given. No
matter what I do, I cannot help but act as a late twentieth century New York
upper middle class assimilated Jew. But as I act, with the other men and women
with whom I am collectively choosing my future, and therefore my history, I
alter that matrix, I do not passively reenact it.
Our
projects become embodied in our choices, and thereby in our history - even in
the very structure of our space and time. And because that structure is
determined by human projects, not by merely theoretical or contemplative
observation, it is inherently perspectival, interested, engaged. There is no
observation post, high above the battle, from which I can gain an objective,
neutral, disinterested view of the struggle below. Every position, including
that one, is a perspective that embodies some choice, some project.[3]
This
last point is central to my argument, and I would like therefore to illustrate
it with examples drawn from the American experience. I hope in our discussion
that some of you will suggest corresponding examples from your own experience.
In
the iconography of official American society, the structure of our historical
time is represented as having six defining moments or nodes: The arrival of the
Pilgrims at Plymouth in 1620, the Revolutionary War of 1776-1783, the Civil War
of 1861-65, the First World War of 1917-18, the Great Depression of the 1930's,
starting with the Stock Market Crash of 1929, and the Second World War,
starting with the Attack on Pearl Harbor by the Japanese on December 7, 1941
and ending with the surrender of the Japanese in 1945. Every event in our
history is located by its relation to those nodal moments. An event is either
Colonial, which is to say Pre-Revolutionary; or it is ante-bellum or
post-bellum, which is to say before or after the Civil War, or it is pre-war,
meaning before World War I, or inter-war, or post-war, which is to say after
World War II. Events derive their significance, their coloration, from this
temporal matrix; it is repeated endlessly in school textbooks, in public
speeches, in the organization of sub-disciplines of American History, and in
the symbolism of movies, novels, and popular music.
Now,
this structure encodes a quite particular evaluative understanding of American
history, based on the projects, the norms, the self-understandings, and the
political associations of only a portion of the population of the United
States. For an African-American, for example, it is the Middle Passage of the
Slave Trade, and not the arrival of the Pilgrims, that marks the major
demarcation in historical time. Nor is the Revolutionary War an event of any
significance to the descendent of slaves, for that war, which liberated the
Colonists from the tyranny of King George - or so the story goes - worked no
noticeable alteration in the condition of the sizable portion of the population
then in bondage.
In
recent years, professional historians have witnessed a series of attacks on the
established construction of the American past. First, so-called Regional
Historians revolted against the tyranny of the New England Colonial Historians
by insisting on the independent significance of the historical development of
the Southern, South Western, and Far Western regions of the country. Then, a
number of radical social historians challenged the hegemony of the monied
classes in the pages of history books by researching and writing the history of
agricultural laborers, seamen, and other members of the lower orders. These
were followed by feminist historians, who undertook to reconstruct the past of
that half of the population usually missing from the historical record. And
finally, Black historians resurrected the diaries, letters, autobiographies,
and fictional writings of slaves and former slaves, again challenging and
revising the official temporal organization of the American past.
All
of these rewritings of the past are expressions of, and elements in, a politics
of the present, grounded in projects, policies, and intentions of groups who
constitute themselves through their politics and thereby collectively create
their past. Not only would it be impossible to identify the culture of
such a group independently of these politics; it would be a mistake to suppose
that its culture, indeed its political culture, existed independently of the
on-going choices and actions of the group.
The
ethnographic concept of culture expresses the ethnographer's search for an
observation point that is simultaneously within, and distanced from, the lives
of the people under investigation - a standpoint from which the ethnographer
can understand his or her subjects without making a life-shaping commitment to
engage his or her own life with theirs. Ethnographers have a term for that
impossible standpoint: "Participant observer."
But
"participant observer" is a contradiction in terms. To be a
participant is to join with one's fellows in collectively making the decisions
and engaging in the actions that create, recreate, shape, and change one's
society. To be an observer is to remain disengaged from the objects of one's
inspection, to have and preserve one's own life, one's own projects, plans,
hopes, and efforts, always to remain aware that one will be going home, that
one may, next season, choose some other group as the object of one's
ethnography.
To
put the point tendentiously, but perhaps less abstractly, the fundamental
choice confronting the anthropologist or anyone else who seeks to understand a
group of people is not whether to be a participant observer or a native,
but whether to be a comrade or a tourist. The essence of tourism is its
atemporality. I arrive in Paris or Las Vegas or Beijing, eager to see the
sights and immerse myself in the local culture. If my travel arrangements have
been successful, I quickly and efficiently experience a series of striking
visual images, sounds, tastes, and smells, all before my tour is over. When I
leave, everything is as it was before, ready for the next tourist. Exactly like
DisneyWorld, except that the streets are not so clean and the sequence of
images not so reliably predictable.
One
last personal anecdote: Five years ago, during my first trip to Africa, I spent
two days at Amboseli National Park in Kenya. All my life, I had dreamed of
seeing the wild animals of the East African plain. I set out the first morning
in an official Land Rover to see the animals, most of which, as it happens, had
moved up to the hills because of heavy rains. At about eleven in the morning,
five Land Rovers, apparently by accident, converged on a clump of bushes off to
one side of the road. As we drew up, three lions suddenly burst from the
bushes, and the fifteen or so of us in the Land Rovers snapped pictures before
they ran off. Afterward, I thought to myself: the drivers of all five Land
Rovers knew where to find the lions, and had obviously agreed beforehand to
meet there at a set time to flush them for the tourists. This must happen six
days a week, every week of the year! What do the lions think? Do they get
vacations? Are there temporary lions that stand in for them when they are on
their annual holiday? Despite their enormous sophistication, their linguistic
facility, and their mastery of local folkways, anthropologists are, in the end,
just tourists in Land Rovers waiting for the lions to appear.
Finally:
What are we to make of the uses to which the concept of culture is put in
contemporary South African discussions? Defenders of Apartheid, of the
entrenched power of the White minority, make much of the notion of culture,
even, in what appears to be not quite irony, applying the dismissive term
"tribe" to themselves in an attempt to justify their demand for a
veto over the actions of a democratic majority. Having attempted for five
decades to partition the country according to imagined cultural essences and
their associated territorial embodiments, they now fall back on the notion of
group rights to rationalize the continued rule of the many by the few.
The
self-serving character of these arguments is so transparent that I at least,
feel no intellectual or political compulsion to take them seriously - although
that may very well reveal the degree to which I am an outsider in South African
life. But how shall we evaluate the recent calls for a national culture,
a culture of liberation, to replace the divisive cultures of the Apartheid
system?
If
this amounts to nothing more than a celebration of literature, visual arts, and
music that has been given less than a fair hearing in the public space of South
Africa, no one can possibly object. But I suspect something more is at work.
From my outsider's perch, as an infrequent visitor to this country, I see a
liberation movement that, in process of overthrowing the tyranny of a small,
powerful minority, too easily loses sight of the conflicts of interest within
the Black majority. I see a highly publicized circle of newly visible, increas-\ingly
powerful men - and, I might say, very few women indeed - who manifestly
represent the interests of only a segment of the total Black population, but
who speak in the name of all, and make decisions for all.
The
call for a national culture obscures these conflicts and divisions, and
inevitably, obscures them in such a way as to enshrine the interests of a
favored sector of the Black population as the interests of all. The idea that
all South Africans are one people with one culture, one history, and therefore
one politics, flies in the face of the reality on the ground.
Several
years ago, the ANC revised the Freedom Charter, giving up socialism and land
reform for democracy. Perhaps that was a necessary accommodation, perhaps not.
I believe only those who must live out its consequences are in a position to
judge. But there can be no doubt that that accommodation benefited the urban,
upwardly mobile, better educated sector of the Black population
disproportionately. If the ANC now undertakes to call into existence a national
culture as the ideal unification of the South African people, it will further
obscure the competing projects, plans, aspirations, and needs of the many segments
of the South Africa, and hegemonically impose one collective vision to the
detriment of all others. In my worst nightmares, I foresee a South African
variant of that bizarre American instrument of political repression, the House
UnAmerican Activities Committee. How much better to set aside the concept of
culture as an inappropriate tool for the understanding of society, and attend
instead to the political projects in which men and women embody their hopes and
aims, and thereby organize their understanding of their collective life.
[1] Close observers of the higher apes
are able to identify clear personality differences that bear some family
resemblance to the personality differences among humans, of course, though it
seems not to be so clear that they can identify "cultural" variations
from band to band of primates.
[2] I might note that in writing this
sentence, I first actually typed out "execretory" for
"excretory," which says a very great deal about the causal and
metaphoric relationship between bodily functions and personality formation!
[3] The full justification for this claim can be found in my
paper, “Narrative Time,” a copy of which was made available to you.
5 comments:
First of all, the quality of your reflections on the concept of culture is impressive, and I'm not familiar enough with anthropology to criticize them or confirm them.
As to your last paragraph expressing your fears that the concept of culture can become a pretext for repression against dissidents or weirdos, if those in power want to repress dissidents or weirdos or heretics of any order, they don't need the concept of culture to do that.
While in the U.S., as you point out, the concept of "American culture" was used to repress dissidents, in the Soviet Union, in Cuba and in Marxist-Leninist parties throughout the world, the concept of deviating men and women from their collective political project, as understood by the hegemonic orthodoxy, was used to repress anybody who got in the way or who might get in the way some day (so-called "objective enemies").
That is, the concept of a collective political project, which you understand as liberating (and which under certain circumstances is liberating, I agree), can become as a sinister an instrument of control and domination as the most narrow-minded concept of culture on record.
Thanks anyway, for posting these three installments.
'Rear a wolf or elephant or shrew or cat in captivity, separated from other members of its species, and either completely or to a quite considerable extent it will grow into a recognizably coherent, appropriately graceful, mature instance of its species. What is more, rear such an animal taken from one population of its species, and it will, when released, become a functional member of whatever other population of its species it is placed in. [This claim is a trifle overstated, for emphasis, and no doubt it fails to take into account some marvelous traits of dolphins, but the point, nevertheless, is, I believe, essentially correct.]'
Not just exaggerated: flat out false. Especially the bit about becoming a functional member of the troupe, herd or whatever on release into hte wild. . This a big part of what is known in the Philosophy of biology as EvoDevo
When I reflect on my adult self, and set myself in comparison to others around me, it is natural for me to perceive all of us as instances of a type, instantiations of a universal form the nature and existence of which is prior to and hence independent of any one of us.
Yes, the primordial nature.
A nice literary description of an ideal type of ethnographer as he appears in your kritique could be the protagonist Phileas Fogg from Jules Verne's novel "Journey Around the Earth in 80 Days". A rich English gentleman who wants to circumnavigate around the globe, and never really manages to get in touch with his surroundings. All the misfortunes, accidents, entanglements, obstacles, misunderstandings that happen on the journey only directly affect his servant Jean Passepartout, whose name already reveals what function he performs for his gentleman
It’s only false because of the examples. A great portion of life can survive without rearing. Another good portion can survive without any real transfer of learning between generations. Elephants are not like this, however.
Post a Comment