Tuesday, October 25, 2022

THE DREAMS OF MY [RELATIVE] YOUTH

 

 

SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY

The Agenda for the ‘Nineties

by

 Robert Paul Wolff

for

The Journal of Social Philosophy

January, 1989


As the new editor of the Journal of Social Philosophy, Peter French has invited a number of us to 'attempt to identify some of the major topics or issues or questions to which those working in social, political, moral, or legal theory ought to be addressing themselves in the next decade.' He does not ask us to suggest answers to these questions, merely to identify the questions. Surely this is, to quote Kant, 'a task which is rather an amusement than a labour.[1] In that spirit, let me try to identify the three theoretical problems whose solution, or at least clarification, constitutes the agenda for social philosophers for the nineties and some considerable time beyond.

Generally speaking, social philosophy, or social theory [I make no distinction between the two], does not exhibit a path of unbroken advance. Quite to the contrary, the level of sophistication and insight of social philosophers seems to me to have reached a peak roughly half a century ago, and, save in one crucially important area, to have declined since. Hence, at least part of the task confronting social philosophers in the coming decades is to recover what was achieved by Max Weber, Karl Mannheim, Herbert Marcuse, and their fellow theorists. The exception, as I shall argue shortly, is the dramatic rediscovery of Karl Marx as an important economic theorist, thanks to the modern analytic reinterpretation of classical and Marxian political economy during the sixties, seventies, and early eighties.

1.      The Problem of the Union of Marx and Freud

Let us begin, then, with the problem which the social theorists of the Frankfort school recognized to be the major intellectual challenge of early twentieth century social theory, and to which they devoted their principal energies: the working out, to put it emblematically, of a rapprochement between Marx and Freud.

The singular power of Marx's critique of early capitalism lay in its attempt to unite a moral and psychological critique of the destructive effects of capitalism on the individual - the theory of alienation and false consciousness - with a systematic analysis of the institutional structure and workings of the capitalist economy as a whole, all in the service of demonstrating both that capitalism rests on the exploitation of the working class and that it is internally unstable and therefore progressively more likely to be replaced by a humane and rational socialism.

There was, of course, a long European tradition of critical analysis of the conditions of individual human fulfillment, starting with Plato and continuing in full strength in the writings of the utopian socialists. There was also a newer tradition - but by Marx's day certainly a century old - of analytic critique of the workings of a capitalist market economy. What made Marx's work unique, and immensely powerful, was the attempt to unite these two in what might somewhat cavalierly be called the Geisteswissenschaftlich version of a 'unified field theory' of the individual and society.

Marx's theory of capitalist economic institutions and practices was on the forefronts of the economic theorizing of his day, although as a consequence of the three-pronged marginalist revolution of Jevons, Menger, and Walras in the decade after the publication of CAPITAL, this fact was obscured until about thirty years ago. But his theory of unalienated human nature, however inspiring and insightful, was merely one more bit of armchair psychologizing. Marx cannot be said to have been more of a theorist of the human condition than Plato, Hobbes, Shakespeare, or Nietzsche - although that is, of course, heady company in which to be placed.

It remained for Freud to put the theory of human personality on a sound scientific basis, and to inaugurate a process of progressively deeper understanding of the formations and deformations of the human psyche that continues to the present day. It is of no consequence that Freud's theories were tentative, limited, to some extent constrained by cultural, sexual, and perhaps class biases, and applicable, in the form in which he articulated them, only to a fraction of the men and women even of his own turn-of-the-century Vienna. Analogous limitations must be placed on the truth claims of all important advances of knowledge. What matters is that with Freud, we move be- yond armchair psychologizing to an irreversible advance in our understanding of human personality.

During the same period of time - roughly the first third of this century - students of economy and society, mostly in Europe, were advancing and refining, but also seriously challenging, Marx's analysis of capitalism. We can identify four developments which, in one way or another, called Marx's theories into question. These were, First, the manifest willingness of the working classes of France and Germany to go to war against one another in the trenches of World War One, in clear contradiction to what any social critic thinking along Marxian lines could see were their true class interests. Second, the failure of the Great Depression - surely the terminal crisis predicted by Marx if anything could be! - to bring about socialist revolutions in the advanced industrial capitalist nations, Third, the growing evidence that capitalism was providing an improving standard of living for the great mass of workers~ and Finally, the unanticipated, and inexplicable, appearance, in the economically least advanced country in Europe, of a regime that pronounced itself Marxist, and proclaimed that it had instituted socialism in one country.

Accompanying these four developments was a fifth, not particularly in contradiction with Marx's analysis of capitalism, but in its enormity crying out for understanding: the rise of Naziism from the ashes of Weimar Germany.

By the late thirties, progressive social theorists had available to them an increasingly sophisticated understanding of human psychopathology and a flawed, but nonetheless .powerful, critique of the economic, political, and legal institutions and practices of capitalism, but no way of relating these two bodies of knowledge and insight to one another. Naziism, which at one and the same time presented itself as an economic and political system [identified with 'socialism'!] and as a monstrous outbreak of criminal pathology, cried out for a unified analysis grounded both in a theory of late capitalism and in a theory of human personality.

A number of the members of the Institute for Social Research - Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer, Erich Fromm, Herbert Marcuse - self-consciously undertook to fuse the Marxian and Freudian traditions into a unified analysis of Naziism in particular and late capitalism in general. The result was some of the most exciting, original, and powerful social theory ever written. THE AUTHORITARIAN PERSONALITY, ESCAPE FROM FREEDOM, EROS AND CIVILIZA- TION, ONE-DIMENSIONAL MAN, together with such works as IDEOLOGY AND UTOPIA and BEHEMOTH, achieved a new level of sophistication, breadth, power, and insight in social theory, a level that has not again been reached.

The first task facing social theory in the next decade, then, is to recover what that generation of thinkers understood, and to carry their work forward. In this effort, it will be necessary to rely both on the enormous advances that have been made in the psychoanalytic and social analysis of personality formation, and on the fullscale reconstruction of Marxian economic theory now under way [see below]. What must be thoroughly eschewed is psychologizing that is 'philosophical' in the bad sense - speculative, ideological, not based on clinical experience. Equally to be avoided is an emphasis on cultural critique to the exclusion of economic and institutional analysis. Too much of what passes these days for radical social theory consists of the sort of Kulturkritik with which Bruno Bauer and his compatriots would have felt right at home. Novels, films, popular culture, and the grotesqueries of 'post-modernism' are not the place to look for insight into what Marx called the laws of motion of capitalism.

What contribution can philosophers make to this effort? For the most part, I consider this question ill-conceived. There can be no division of labor that leaves professional philosophers with purely philosophical questions nicely dissected out of the body politic. But there are complex methodological and epistemological issues complexly interwoven into the attempt to understand the relationship between the institutional and the individual, and thoughtful, knowledgeable philosophers can surely help to think them through.

Finally, why a union of Marx and Freud, rather than [say] Jung and Parsons, or Ricardo and Foucault? Because Freud and Marx stand head and shoulders above all the other theorists of the past century and a half, and because their work places at the center of its investigations the mystifications, self-deceptions, false consciousness, and ideological misrepresentations which are the defining mark of the social in human experience.

2.      The Problem of Up-Dating Marx

The second major problem, to which an enormous amount of highly creative intellectual energy is now being devoted, is the full-scale re-thinking of Marx's critique of capitalism so as to make it directly and usefully applicable to the social and economic realities of the late twentieth and early twenty-first centuries. This is an effort that must proceed on a number of different fronts, theoretical, empirical, and historical, involving the labors of thinkers in, at the very least, Economics, Sociology, History, Political Science, and Philosophy.

Marx was, first and foremost, a political economist, a theoretical economist seeking to identify the statics and dynamics of the capitalist economic system as it was developing in his day. His work was, quite self-consciously, at one and the same time the completion of the classical system laid down by the Physiocrats, Smith, and Ricardo and the creation of a new theoretical system, both through the posing of new questions and by the introduction of new theoretical concepts.[2]

Like the other theoretical economists of the first half of the nineteenth century, Marx lacked the mathematical techniques for articulating the formal relationships that constituted the heart of his economic theory. Consequently, it was possible for early critics mistakenly to impute elementary internal inconsistencies to his theories, particularly as regards the relationship between the doctrines of Volumes One and Three of CAPITAL.

Furthermore, the success of marginalism after the eighteen seventies put the entire classical tradition into eclipse. Not only Marx, but also Ricardo, Mill, Smith and the other classical political economists ceased to be read as marginalism established itself as the theoretical orthodoxy of western economics. By the middle of the twentieth century, it was possible for so brilliant an economist as Paul Samuelson to scoff at Marx as an 'autodidact' and a 'minor post-Ricardian.'

But the inadequacies of marginalism, manifested in its inability to explain the persistant catastrophic unemployment of the Great Depression, together with the application of new techniques of mathematical analysis to the internal interconnections of the sectors of a developed capitalist economy, gave birth to a rediscovery of Marx that has, in the past three decades, transformed the theoretical landscape. Beginning with Wassily Leontiev's use of techniques of linear analysis in his 'input-output' model of a capitalist economy, and followed by the [apparently quite independent] working-out of a similar ·1inear model by Piero Sraffa, mathematical economists around the world have rediscovered in the classical school of Ricardo and Marx a formally sound alternative to the orthodox marginalist model. Michio Morishima, Andras Brody, Luigi Pasinetti, Pierangelo Garegnani, John Roemer, Stephen Marglin and scores of other economists from a dozen countries have elaborated a theoretical model that is beginning to rival marginalism not only in fundamental analytic power but also in the complexity and diversity of its detail.[3]

Leaving to one side the mathematics, the key to the difference between marginalism and modern Marxism [if I may thus label the new model] is the nature of the questions it asks about capitalism. Marginalism construes Economics as 'the science which studies human behaviour as a relationship between ends and scarce means which have alternative uses.’[4] In other words, it looks at the economy from the point of view of a capitalist trying to make a profit by choosing the right way to employ his capital. Marginalism wants to know how the individual capitalist can maximize his profits, how the individual consumer can maximize his or her satisfaction, and what the systemic consequences will be of the interactions among large numbers of similarly motivated choices by a society of capitalists and consumers. For the marginalist, neither economic growth nor the society-wide shape of the distribution of the social product is a matter of direct or central concern, although marginalists will undertake, in a limited way, to infer conclusions about those matters from their model.

The classical economists conceive Economics quite differently. For them, it is primarily the study of the way in which a society endlessly engaged in reproducing itself divides up the social product, cycle after cycle, among the several great classes of men and women that make up the social whole, and secondarily the study of the way that this social division either promotes or impedes economic growth.

If one reflects on the nature of the economic problems that have confronted the world in the post-World War II period, it is not surprising that an economic theory centered on problems of distribution and growth should have generated such wide interest. Nor ought we to be surprised that interest has waned in a model, however sophisticated, that takes concepts of equilibrium and efficient selection of alternative investment strategies as central.

Powerful as Marx's theories are as an instrument for analysing and criticizing capitalism, there is obviously an enormous gap between any theory, however successful, of mid-nineteenth century capitalism, and the reality of the late twentieth-century world economy. In order to simplify matters somewhat and organize what is really an enormous subject, we can identify three species of inadequacy which Marxian economic theory exhibits, each of which calls for major theoretical work in the years ahead.

First, and simplest, is Marx's failure to incorporate what he himself identified as his major theoretical contribution into the formal structure of his own model. According to Marx, the key to understanding the functioning of capitalism, and to demonstrating that capitalist profits rest on the exploitation of the working class, is the distinction between productive labor, or the purposeful activity of transforming nature so as to make it into commodities capable of being sold for a profit in the marketplace, and labor-power, or the worker's capacity for productive labor. The worker sells his or her labor-power to the capitalist, who then undertakes, in the workplace, to extract from that labor-power as much productive labor as he possibly can. The secret to the origin of profit, according to Marx, lies in the gap between the quantity of past labor embodied in, or required to produce, that labor-power, and the larger quantity of living labor that the capitalist extracts from the labor-power when he puts it to work in his factory. Put somewhat less abstractly, profit results from the fact that workers create more new value than they consume to keep themselves alive and working for yet another day. The capitalist appropriates the difference, and gets rich.

Marx was not able to see, but we, with modern analytic techniques can now prove rigorously, that this account of the origin of profit actually makes no use at all of the labor/labor-power distinction on which, or so he thought, his entire theory was based. The first task for modern Marxists, therefore, is to complete Marx's own theoretical enterprise by successfully building the labor/labor-power distinction into a formal model of capitalism in an illuminating and theoretically significant way.

This task is currently being carried out by several of the best Marxist economists in the United States, among them Samuel Bowles of the University of Massachusetts and Ed Nell of the New School for Social Research. Bowles, Nell, and others have figured out how to make an analytic connection between the theory of the origin of profit on the one hand, and Marx's brilliantly vivid, but largely anecdotal accounts of the power struggle within the factory on the other,

The second inadequacy of Marx's economic theory - an inadequacy shared by all of the classical theory of his day and the marginalist and neo-classical theory that followed - is its failure to incorporate into its model of the functioning of captalism any account of three essential institutional components of capitalist society: the capitalist firm, the working-class family, and the state. The state, the firm, and the family are obviously essential components of any adequate model of a capitalist economy, but none of them is provided with a theoretical analysis by Marx, or by any of his predecessors or marginalist successors.

Marx, like the laisser-faire theorists, posited a state that was no more than a night-watchman, or alternatively, a committee of the bourgeoisie. Marx entirely failed to foresee the central role of the state as a fiscal and monetary force in late capitalism. In recent years, a number of Marxist economists have attempted to incorporate some conception of the state as an independent center of decision and action into their theory of capitalism, most notably James O'Connor.[5] Clearly, a great deal more needs to be done in the coming decades.

The family poses an entirely different set of theoretical and -empirical problems. As Marx recognizes, the family is the locus of the reproduction of labor-power. Hence, its role is essential to the continued operation of a capitalist economy. But despite his bitter and penetrating observations on bourgeois family life in the COMMUNIST MANIFESTO, and the moving accounts of the effects of capitalism on women and children in CAPITAL and in Engels' THE CONDITION OF THE WORKING CLASS IN ENGLAND, there is no theoretical space in Marx's model of capitalism for the family as a complex unit within which potentially exploitative transfers of value take place. Marx was not simply personally insensitive to the position of women [as painfully captured by Jerrold Seigel in his brilliant biography, MARX'S FATE.[6]] His model of capitalist exploitation does not allow for an analysis of the exploitation of women by men within the family. A number of Marxist feminists, among them Nancy Folbre, have in recent years begun the complex task of reconstructing Marxian theory in order to make room for a theoretical analysis of the exploitation of women.[7]

Finally, there is a pressing need for some theoretical analysis along Marxian lines of the capitalist firm. In the past century and more, the firm has been transformed from a small privately owned operation functioning essentially as the extension of the will of the entrepreneur into an enormous bureaucratic entity with inner dynamics and organizational imperatives that bear only a glancing relationship to the simple profit maximatization posited by Marx, the classicals, and the neo-classicals alike. John Kenneth Galbraith, Herbert Simon, and other non-Marxist economists have done valuable work on the modern firm, although little headway has been made in incorporating what are essentially historical and anecdotal accounts of the firm into a theory of price formation and profit. But Marxist economists have only begun the job of theorizing about the firm. Notable, along these lines, is Stephen Marglin's classic essay.[8]

But more difficult even than correcting internal inadequacies in Marx's theory. or broadening it to incorporate elements of the capitalist economy which he ignored, despite the fact that they existed in his day, is the task of transforming Marxian political economy to take account of the enormous changes in capitalism since the middle of the nineteenth century.

Let me mention just four of these changes, by way of indicating the sorts of theoretical and conceptual tasks that lie ahead for Marxian theorists.

Most striking. surely, is the reversal of the trend toward polarization between rich and poor, capitalist and worker, which Marx observed and which he thought to be one of the central tendencies of capitalist development. In the middle of the nineteenth century, it was entirely plausible to claim, as Marx did, that capitalism was destroying traditional crafts, erasing the distinction between skilled and unskilled labor. driving small businesses to the wall, proletarianizing the peasantry, capitalizing the landed aristocracy, and progressively transforming bourgois society into two homogeneous and opposed classes.

But the past century has, quite to the contrary, seen the creation and preservation of a highly pyramidal structure of inequality of income and wealth, in which there are not two homogeneous classes but a hierarchy of strata or class fragments defined by the inequality of their shares in wages and salaries rather than merely by the inequality in their ownership of the means of production. The shares of national income going to the different deciles, or income tenths, in the United States, for example, has not changed notably in the past eighty years, save for a slow erosion in the share going to the poorest tenth, and a small increase in the share going to the richest tenth.

As a consequence, it begins to make sense to talk not only about capital's exploitation of labor, but also about salaried workers' exploitation of wage laborers, and union laborers' exploitation of the non-unionized. A number of Marxist economists have begun to analyze the phenomenon of relative exploitation, but there is a good deal more work that needs to be done.[9]

The second major development in the past century is the evolution of the financial system, and the emergence of forms of money which were unknown in Marx's day. Money remains a problem for economists, both orthodox and Marxist. Marx himself set forth a quantity theory of money that would sound comfortable coming from the mouth of Milton Friedman. Although he recognized, more perhaps than any other classical economist, the central conceptual and theoretical role of money ~ such in a capitalist economy, his own theory never gets beyond a commodity theory of money [i.e., money=gold as a reproducible commodity). Recent Marxist theorists have been no more successful in their efforts to understand the nature of money. Monetary theorists like Suzanne de Brunhof can advance very little beyond an explication of Marx's own texts.

Marginalists and modern general equilibrium theorists, of course, make no place at all for money as such in their models, a fact which rather puzzled me when I first encountered them. Ironically, the linear reproduction models of Leontief, Sraffa, et al. make no place for money either. The formal implication of their analyses is that money is merely accidental to the operations of a capitalist economy, a proposition which Marx would have insisted was absurd. Nevertheless, insisting is no substitute for theorizing, and an adequate Marxist understanding of money still waits to be advanced.

The third dramatic change in capitalism between Marx's day and ours is the through-going internationalization of the world capitalist economy. Marx foresaw this, of course, predicted it and insisted upon its inevitability. But the process was barely begun in his own day, and we need, today, a full-scale Marxist theory of the international economy. The most interesting attempts in this direction are the many works in recent years devoted to the relationship between the capitalist nations and the primary-producing nations of the so-called Third World.[10]

The internationalization of capitalism requires not only a re-thinking of the relationship of national economies to the world economy, but also a reanalysis of the structure of exploitation within individual countries. It is by now a commonplace that all of us in the affluent First World, workers and capitalists alike, enjoy the standard of living we do in part because we - all of us - exploit the working classes of the primary-producing Third World nations. The gap between the standard of living of First and Third World workers - greater by far than the gap between the well-off and the less-well-off within the First World - poses moral as well as conceptual questions about the appropriateness of the term 'exploitation' as a description of the relationship between rich and poor in the developed nations.

Finally, contemporary Marxist theorists must come to terms with the manifest fact that the conditions of existence of workers in the bourgeois capitalist nations have improved dramatically in the past century, contrary to the confident predictions of Marx and Engels. Sophisticated discourses about 'relative immiseration' and 'repressive desublimation' cannot conceal the fact that both the daily work and the real [i.e., material] rewards of the great mass of working people have improved greatly since Marx wrote, Stripped of all its theoretical trappings, CAPITAL is a book about the manifest human misery of early capitalism. When Marx and Engels cry out, 'The Proletarians have nothing to lose but their chains!,' they do not have in mind workers who have achieved home ownership, some measure of old age security, at least partial medical insurance, and the possibility of sending their children to the local Community College.

Those of us, like myself, who believe that the concept of exploitation remains the central theoretical tool for understanding capitalism are under a heavy obligation either to justify the moral baggage carried by that term in contemporary capitalism or else to stop using it.

It will be noted that I have not included, in my list of changes re- quiring theoretical rethinking, the appearance on the world scene of a number of major and minor national economies proclaiming themselves Marxist, socialist, or communist. None of them bears any more relation to what Marx had in mind than modern Christianity does to the pronouncements of Jesus. Indeed, the economies of the Soviet Union, China, and the other nations of the so-called Socialist Bloc merely serve as a negative confirmation of Marx's unwavering conviction that socialism could only emerge as an inner development out of the late stages of the playing out of the logic of capitalism.

3.      Methodological Individualism and the Theory of Society

The third major task facing social theory in the coming decade is at once the most intractable and the philosophically most interesting: the working out of the ontological status of society, as an object of investigation, that preserves the immensely valuable insights of the great continental tradition of social theory while conforming to the dictates of a conceptually coherent methodological individualism. Put somewhat more epigrammatically, we might think of this as the task of making Marx lie down with Mill.

For the first two thousand years and more of western philosophy, the admissible elements of a defensible ontology - leaving to one side God - were nature and the individual. Some, like Hobbes, might undertake to reduce the latter to the former, while others - Berkeley comes to mind - could be construed as absorbing the former into the latter. But even as late as the end of the eighteenth century, society does not figure as an independent category of being - a kind of thing sui generis, not to be reduced to, or explained in terms of, either nature or the individual.

A century later, all that has changed. Philosophy - like social theory, art history, anthropology, and history - has discovered society as an autonomous object of theoretical investigation. The most dramatic proclamation of the ontological autonomy of the social occurs in the writings of Emile Durkheim, for whom the existence of an autonomous realm of social facts is the necessary precondition for the existence of Sociology as a genuine discipline.

Each individual drinks, sleeps, eats, reasons, and it is to society's interest that these functions be exercised in an orderly manner. If, then, all these facts are counted as 'social' facts, sociology would have no subject matter exclusively its own, and its domain would be confused with that of biology and psychology. But in reality there is in every society a certain group of phenomena which may be differentiated from those studied by the other natural sciences… Here, then, is a category of facts with very distinctive characteristics: it consists of ways of acting, thinking, and feeling, external to the individual, and endowed with a power of coercion, by reason of which they control him••• [T]heir source is not in the individual, their substratum can be no other than society, either the political society as a whole or some one of the partial groups it includes…[11]

Collective tendencies have an existence of their own~ they are forces as real as cosmic forces, though of an- other sort~ they, likewise, affect the individual from without, though through other channels. The proof that the reality of collective tendencies is no less than that of cosmic forces is that this reality is demonstrated in the same way, by the uniformity of effects…[12]

Durkheim's language is in fact ambiguous with respect to the actual independent existence of a collective unconscious as the bearer of these collective tendencies, but his insistence on the non-reducibility of the social to the psychological [or, needless to say, to the physical] poses in a strong form the fundamental epistemological and methodological problem for social philosophers.

The problem can be put in this way: can we give an explication of social phenomena which rigorously avoids the positing, either implicitly or explicitly, in an ontologically queer manner such entities as collective mind, Geist, History, Capital, The Proletariat, etc., while at the same time preserving all that is legitimate and important about society and social phenomena in the tradition of social theory growing out of Marx, Durkheim, Tonnies, Weber, and their successors? Can we make sense of mystification without reducing it to individual illusion, ideology without reducing it to individual false consciousness? Can we find a way of expressing Mannheim's insights into the social roots of knowledge that does not commit us to the existence of the collective unconscious to which he refers in IDEOLOGY AND UTOPIA?[13]

The most sophisticated recent attempt to bring the insights of the Franco-German tradition within the methodological purview of analytic philosophy is Jon Elster's important book, MAKING SENSE OF MARX.[14] Elster opens with an admirably clear statement of the methodological principle involved, and much of the more than five hundred pages that follow is devoted to detailed explications and critiques of passages in Marx's writings which ap- pear, at least at first reading, to violate the individualist precept. Here is Elster's preliminary statement:

By [methodological individualism] I mean the doctrine that all social phenomena - their structure and their change - are in principle explicable in ways that involve only individuals - their properties, their goals, their beliefs and their actions. Methodological individualism thus conceived is a form of reductionism.[15]

The key to Elster's approach is modern rational choice theory, in particular Game Theory [or at least the concepts and rhetoric of Game Theory - there is no attempt actually to construct formally correct models of games or to invoke the theorems, such as they are, of Game Theory.] Elster exhibits considerable imagination and flair in his deployment of the notion of unintended consequences. His particular target is functional explanation, embodying as it does the assumption - illegitimate to a methodological individualist - of teleology not grounded in the intentions or purposes of individuals.

While Elster does yeoman service in demonstrating how far it is possible go in the explication of group phenomena with nothing but the tools of individual rational choice theory, he complete fails, in my judgment, to capture what is distinctive about the social. By reducing mystification, and the opacity of social phenomena, to one or another species of intellectual error or ignorance, he allows to slip away precisely those features of collective life which are definitive of our experience of the social.

Of course, Elster might quite legitimately reply that it is easy enough to reject his explications and insist that something 'more' remains to be captured. It is a good deal harder to say exactly what that something more is, and how his explications have missed it. Perhaps any fully satisfactory philosophical account of the category of mystification will leave us vaguely dissatisfied precisely by virtue of having dispelled the mystery. Nevertheless, I suggest that a fully adequate unpacking of the social remains one of the most pressing tasks of social philosophy in the coming decades.

Well, there it is, a budget of problems, tasks, and unanswered questions that should do quite nicely to keep social philosophers busy until the end of the second milennium. One might make two observations my selection of problems: First, they are all just various ways of saying that we must think about Marx, and second, they seem to require much more than a passing acquaintance with a variety of theoretical and empirical materials not ordinarily considered to lie within the borders of Philosophy.

Both of these observations are quite correct. I am convinced now, as I have been for some years, that Marx is the most original social theorist ever to have lived, and that we cannot do better than to carry forward the complex, many-sided enterprise he began almost one hundred fifty years ago. Since Marx himself was a thinker of enormous breadth, for whom disciplinary boundaries simply did not exist, we must, in our effort to advance his insights, be equally universal in the range of our learning, at least to the best of our ability [for few among us will come close to matching his scope, let alone his power, as a thinker].

With luck, and Peter French's careful guidance, the pages of this journal will be filled, in the years to come, with essays and reviews that seek, one way or another, to come to grips with the problems I have outlined here.



[1] KrV., Axxi. Kant is there referring to the task of providing a complete analysis of the derivative concepts of the system of the Critical Philosophy - he has a rather heroic and Germanic notion of what counts as an amusement!

[2] Needless to say, these characterizations of Marx's thought, like any that might be given, are highly controversial, and open to powerful criticisms from a variety of points of view. My justification for the account of Marx adumbrated in this essay can be found in two books: UNDERSTANDING MARX, Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J., 1984 and MONEYBAGS MUST BE SO LUCKY, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, MA., 1988.

[3] See, among many other works, Wassily Leontief, THE STRUCTURE OF AMERICAN ECONOMY 1919-1929, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA., 1941, Piero Sraffa, PRODUCTION OF COMMODITIES BY MEANS OF COMMODITIES, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1960, Michio Morishima, MARX'S ECONOMICS, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; 1973, Luigi Pasinetti, LECTURES ON THE THEORY OF PRODUCTION, Columbia University Press, New York, NY, 1977, Andras Brody, PROPORTIONS, PRICES, AND PLANNING, American Elsevier, New York, NY, 1970, John Roemer, A GENERAL TIIEORY OF EXPLOITATION AND CLASS, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1982, and Stephen Marglin, GROWTH, DISTRIBUTION, AND PRICES, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1984.

[4] Lionel Robbins, AN ESSAY ON THE NATURE AND SIGNIFICANCE OF ECONOMIC SCIENCE, MacMillan, London, 1932, p. 16

[5] See James O’Connor, THE FISCAL CRISIS OF THE STATE, St Martin’s Press, NY, 1973.

[6] Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1978.

[7] Cf. Nancy Folbre, ‘Explitation comes home: a critique of the Marxian theory of family labour,’ CAMBRIDGE JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS, Volume 6, Number 4 [December, 1982], pp. 317-329.

[8] Stephen Marglin, ‘What do bosses do? The origins and functions of hierarchy in capitalist production,' REVIEW OF RADICAL POLITICAL ECONOMICS, Part 1, Volume 6, pp. 60-112, Part 2, Volume 7, pp. 20-37.

[9] For an extremely suggestive formal treatment, see Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis, 'The Marxian theory of value and heterogeneous labour: a critique and reformulation,' CAMBRIDGE JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS, Volume 1 [1977], pp. 173-192.

[10] See, for example, Samir Amin, UNEQUAL DEVELOPMENT, trans. by Brian Pearce, Monthly Review Press, NY, NY, 1976.

[11] Emile Durkheim, THE RULES OF SOCIOLOGICAL METHOD, eighth edition, trans. by Sarah A. Solovay and John Mueller, ed. by George E. G. Catlin, Glencoe, Ill., The Free Press, 1938, pp. 1-3.

[12] Emile Durkheim, SUICIDE, trans. by John A. Spaulding and George Simpson, Glencoe, Ill., The Free Press, 19S1, p. 309.

 

[13] Cf. Karl Mannheim, IDEOLOGY AND UTOPIA, trans. by Louis Wirth and Edward Shils, Harcourt, Brace and Co., New York, 1936, p. 31. But seep. 48: 'there is no such thing as a 'folk mind' and groups as wholes are as incapable of self-clarification as they are of thinking.' Mannheim is perhaps the most complex and rewarding student of this central methodological problem.

[14] Jon Elster, MAKING SENSE OF MARX, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1985.

[15] Ibid., p. 5.

4 comments:

  1. Splendidly ingenuous to accuse Freud of putting anything on a sound scientific basis.

    ReplyDelete
  2. 'When Marx and Engels cry out, 'The Proletarians have nothing to lose but their chains!,' they do not have in mind workers who have achieved home ownership, some measure of old age security, at least partial medical insurance, and the possibility of sending their children to the local Community College.'

    This is not just chains, it is ball, and etc.

    ReplyDelete
  3. You mention four developments, but I’m surprised you didn’t mention a fifth, namely, the great split in the ranks of the social democrats between those who went for communism and those who rejected it. In fact, or so it seems to me, that rift has something to do with the responses to the great depression, the post-War/Cold War inspired effort to buy off the western working classes, and the marginalisation of the Soviet Union which had at least something to do with the turn towards socialism in one country. I’m not claiming it’s the most important factor, but surely it was a contributing factor?

    ReplyDelete
  4. There are things of which I may not speak;
    There are dreams that cannot die;
    There are thoughts that make the strong heart weak,
    And bring a pallor into the cheek,
    And a mist before the eye.
    And the words of that fatal song
    Come over me like a chill:
    “A boy's will is the wind's will,
    And the thoughts of youth are long, long thoughts."

    My Lost Youth – Henry Wadsworth Longfellow

    ReplyDelete