The Indexing Problem
The Indexing Problem
Dr. Robert Paul Wolff
Presented to
Professor
Buchanan has explicated for us, both in his paper today and in the book which
this session serves to celebrate, the limitations of the sorts of unanimity
partial orderings to which Vilfredo Pareto has given his name. In my remarks
today, I should like to explore some of the ways in which economists and
philosophers have sought to extend the scope of inter- systematic comparisons,
and to suggest reasons for believing that intersystemic comparisons must always
implicitly or otherwise embody some evaluative presuppositions. My thesis is
one more instance of a much broader theme, to which I have many times returned
in writing and teaching, namely that supposedly value-neutral models of formal
analysis usually contain powerful unacknowledged value assumptions which shape
their formal structure as well as their substantive content.
The
problem with unanimity partial orderings is that although they are transitive,
they are not complete. If everyone at our picnic prefers chocolate ice cream to
vanilla, then we can be sure that switching the dessert from vanilla to
chocolate will produce an increase in social welfare, assuming that everything
else remains unchanged, and that there are no externalities. Furthermore, if we
all prefer vanilla to pistachio as well, then the transitivity of individual
preference guarantees that we will all prefer chocolate to pistachio, and
therefore a switch of the dessert from pistachio to chocolate must increase
social welfare. But suppose some of us prefer chocolate to vanilla and the rest
prefer vanilla to chocolate. How shall we evaluate the move from vanilla to
chocolate, as a collective or group decision?
Obviously,
it becomes necessary, at the very least, to ask how much the chocolate
lovers prefer chocolate to vanilla, and the vanilla lovers vanilla to
chocolate. Some cardinal measure of preference intensity, pleasure, welfare,
preference priority, or even, a la Plato and Mill, the
relative objective value of the desire for chocolate versus the desire for
vanilla, will have to be invoked if we are to aggregate the preferences or
desires of the individuals at the picnic into a single group ranking suitable
for the making of a collective social choice. In short, we shall have to define
an index.
Bentham
assumed that pleasure is the only good, pain the only evil, and that
pleasure and pains, no matter whom they afflict, are intersubjectively
comparable and hence commensurable. These assumptions do not, of themselves,
suffice for the construction of an index, of course. It was still necessary for
Bentham to stipulate an aggregation rule or, in the modem jargon, a social
welfare function. His version of utilitarianism is just such a rule. We might state
it in modern terms something like this:
1.
As between two policies, actions, or states of affairs, A and B, if B provides
to each individual in the society at least as much net happiness as does A, and
if there is at least one person to whom B provides more net happiness than does
A, then assign B a higher index number than A.
2.
As between two policies, actions, or states of affairs, A and B, one of which
provides more net happiness to some individuals and the other of which provides
more net happiness to other individuals, measure the amounts of happiness
accorded by each alternative to each individual, using the same scale of measurement.
Then [this, strictly speaking, is the aggregation or indexing rule], following
the rule ' everybody to count for one, nobody for more than one,' add the
quantities of net happiness accorded by each alternative to all the individuals
in the society, and assign to A or B whichever has the larger sum.
We
are accustomed, in the light of the New Welfare Economics of the late
nineteenth and early twentieth century, to focus our attention on the phrase,
'using the same scale of measurement,' and then to invoke the supposed logical
impossibility of interpersonal comparisons of utility as a reason for rejecting
classical utilitarianism. But as Sen, Suppes, Harsanyi, and a number of other
theorists have shown us, there are ways of getting around the problems of
interpersonal comparisons which pose no greater philosophical difficulties than
the extreme solipsism that generates the problem in the first place. The real
problem is the purely normative clause, 'everybody to count for one, nobody for
more than one.' We can defend the assumption that the welfare of the society
consists in the arithmetic sum of the welfares of its individual members only
by positing the moral and political premise that all individuals are equally
important, or that each individual's happiness deserves to be given equal
weight in the social sum. And this premise simply begs all of the questions of policy
that utilitarianism was designed to resolve.
Let
us take a look, now, at a number of practical and theoretical contexts in which
the indexing problem arises. My aim is to show you that in each case, a
resolution of the problem requires a normative or prescriptive premise which
must be exogenously introduced, as economists like to say.
My
first example is drawn from the work of John Rawls. Rawls, you will recall,
undertakes to extract a normative principle of distributive justice from
non-normative, or minimally normative, premises, by means of the conceptual
device of a bargaining game among rationally self-interested agents. In order
to avoid certain theoretical difficulties which stand in the way of his
establishing the principle that he wishes to promulgate, Rawls introduces into
his theoretical construction a limitation on the knowledge available to the
participants in the bargaining game which he labels 'the veil of ignorance.'
Unfortunately,
the veil of ignorance deprives the players in the game of so much information
that they no longer have any rational reason to care about its outcome. So
Rawls is forced to re-equip them with knowledge that they have coherent
life-plans whose fulfillment they are rationally committed to pursuing. But
even this information is insufficient, for what one wishes to bargain for
depends on what in particular one has chosen as a life plan. Hence Raw1s must
add the notion of primary goods, which is to say those things - 'rights and
liberties, opportunities and powers, income and wealth' - which, as he says ' a
rational man wants whatever else he wants.' The idea is simply that no matter
what life plan one turns out to have chosen, possession of these primary goods
will serve to advance it.
But
now the indexing problem rears its head. Clearly, as between two principles of
distributive justice, A and B, if B promises at least as much of each primary
good as does A, and more of at least one, then B is to be preferred to A. But
suppose B promises more opportunity and less wealth, or greater income but less
power. How then shall the rational man behind the veil of ignorance choose? [I
say 'rational man,' because as a careful reader of A THEORY OF JUSTICE will
discover, Rawls' world contains only men.] The answer is to construct an index
of primary goods. It is this number which the individuals in the original
position bargain over.
Although
Rawls is aware of the problems of indexing, he glosses over them, admitting
that we must ' rely on our intuitive capacities.' Nevertheless, he stands by
the fundamental claim on which his entire philosophy rests, namely that his
theory allows him' to replace moral judgments by those of rational prudence...'
[THEORY OF JUSTICE p. 94]
Rawls'
actual discussion of the indexing problem is arbitrary in the extreme. First he
stipulates, with very little ground, that bargainers in the original position
will choose to make rights and liberties lexically prior to all other primary
goods. This has the effect of eliminating the need for an index that aggregates
rights and liberties with the other primary goods, for lexical priority stipulates
that any increase in rights and liberties, however small, will take precedence,
for example, over any loss of wealth or income, however large.
This
still leaves the problem of aggregating wealth and income with opportunities
and powers. Since this is manifestly impossible - how, for example, shall we
compare an increase of ten percent in the opportunity to pursue a medical
career as against a decrease in income of five thousand dollars a year? - Rawls
makes yet another simplifying assumption. Reminding us that the Difference
Principle concerns itself primarily with the least well-off representative man,
Rawls simply asserts that the least advantaged tend to have both the least
wealth and income and the least powers and opportunities. In short, Rawls
assumes away any indexing problem at all.
But clearly
the issue is not so simply resolved. One of the major points of controversy in
modem social welfare policy concerns precisely the relationship, in the lives
of the least advantaged, of income or power. Radical critics of current welfare
practices have argued that transfer payments, particularly payments in kind,
have the effect of depriving the poor of social and political power, and indeed
may even have that as their purpose. Hence, as between two social policies, one
of which increases the income of the least advantaged while making them impotent
clients of the welfare bureaucracy, the other of which increases economic or
political power but at the cost of a lowered income, it becomes a matter of substantive
and evaluative social philosophy which to espouse.
Rawls
himself has finally recognized the inescapably normative element in his notion
of life plans and primary goods. In a recent volume of essays titled
UTILITARIANISM AND BEYOND, edited by Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, Rawls
returns to the subject in an essay on 'Social Unity and Primary Goods.' In the
following passages, Rawls virtually acknowledges that the formation of an index
of primary goods presupposes normative constraints on what will count as an
acceptable life plan.
Imagine
two persons, one satisfied with a diet of milk, bread and beans, while the
other is distraught without expensive wines and exotic dishes. In short one has
expensive tastes, the other does not. If the two principles of justice are
understood in their simplest form (as I assume here), then we must say, the
objection runs, that with equal incomes both are equally satisfied. But this is
plainly not true.... The reply is that as moral persons citizens have some part
in forming and cultivating their final ends and preferences. It is not by
itself an objection to the use of primary goods that it does not accommodate
those with expensive tastes. One must argue in addition that it is
unreasonable, if not unjust, to hold such persons responsible for their
preferences and to require them to make out as best they can. But to argue this
seems to presuppose that citizens' preferences are beyond their control as
propensities or cravings which simply happen.
And
Rawls continues:
The
idea of holding citizens responsible for their ends is plausible, however, only
on certain assumptions. First, we must assume that citizens can regulate and
revise their ends and preferences in the light of expectations of primary
goods. [And so forth]
In
short we can hope to arrive at a usable definition of an index of primary
goods, only if we require that our prudentially self-interested bargainers
constrain their life-plans by considerations of fairness and, as Rawls says a
bit later in the same essay,” the higher-order interests of moral persons.” I
think we can fairly conclude that Rawls has failed, in his own words, 'to
replace moral judgments by those of rational prudence.'
The
same indexing problem surfaces in a quite different context, in the proposal
currently being debated to award women equal pay for jobs comparable in worth
to those performed by men. It may not be immediately obvious that the
comparable worth dispute is really an argument about indexing, but a few
moments of reflection will make this clear.
Consider
a firm that employs three groups of workers: machine operators, truck drivers,
and office clerks. What wages shall it pay? The answer popular with
neo-classical economists is, of course, Let the labor market decide. The firm
should offer the lowest wage with which it can secure competent help. If the
going market price, say for machine operators, is so high that the firm cannot
make a profit when paying that wage, then it must either shift to a different
production technique or else go out of business. If some extremely simplifying
assumptions are made about the production techniques available to the firm, the
behavior of workers and consumers, and the motivation of the firm's managers,
then in long-run equilibrium, each worker will earn a wage precisely equal to
his or her marginal product, which, under some additional strong assumptions,
might plausibly be construed as a fair wage.
There
are essentially three things wrong with this story, which you will all recognize
as the standard story told in beginning courses in economic theory. The three
things wrong with the story are, First, that it fails to establish its
normative claims even in the impossibly restrictive theoretical case of which
it is supposed to hold, Second, that it does not hold at all for theoretical
cases whose assumptions are somewhat less restrictive, and Third, that it bears
no relation at all to what happens in the real world.
For
a demonstration of the first claim, I refer you to the first chapter of David
Schweickart's fine book, CAPITALISM OR WORK CONTROL? The third claim, that
marginal productivity theory totally fails to predict what actually happens, is
widely acknowledged. For an extended discussion, you can consult Lester Thurow's
suggestive work, GENERATING INEQUALITY, or a forthcoming Oxford Press Book,
CHOOSING THE RIGHT POND, by a young Cornell economist, Robert Frank.
I
wish to focus my attention on the second problem - the inadequacy of marginal
productivity theory for more complicated theoretical cases. What I wish to show
you is that under certain theoretical assumptions designed to model more
accurately the modem firm, a problem of wages policy arises which, in its
broadest outlines, is inescapably normative, and in which the issue of
comparable worth plays a central role. There, as we shall see, indexing again
proves to be the stumbling block.
So
long as firms are small, single-product producers purchasing all inputs,
including semi-finished parts, at competitive market prices, performing a
single transformation on the inputs, and selling the output at the same
competitive prices, the theory of wage determination is relatively simple. But
things go seriously awry as soon as firms grow large enough to engage in
multi-stage production processes with joint product outputs.
Consider
a meatpacking firm, for example, that fattens the cattle, slaughters them,
butchers the carcasses, packs the cuts of meat, and tans the hides. The
managers of the firm must ascertain, by means if their internal accounting
system, how much of the total cost of the firm to allocate to each final
product, and also what prices to place on intermediate products within the firm
for purpose of cost accounting.
Under
these circumstances, it is theoretically impossible to determine the marginal
productivity of a worker. Indeed, as firms grow into large bureaucratically
organized institutions, it may in practice be impossible to identify any change
in final output that can be associated with the presence or absence of a
particular employee. Clearly, what is required is a positive wage policy which
dictates what level of compensation is to be associated with each position in
the firm.
The
first rule that suggests itself- a normative rule, be it noted - is equal pay
for equal work, where equal work is interpreted as meaning the occupying of
bureaucratically identical positions. All beginning truck drivers, all clerks
of grade three, all machine operators working the same machines, will receive
equal pay. It is a good deal harder than one might think to come up with a
moral rationale for this principle, although considerations of prudence and
labor/management peace might suggest it. If the firm were dispensing justice,
then one might invoke familiar considerations of procedural fairness, but in a
competitive economy, mutual self- interest, and not justice, is supposed to
regulate the relations between labor and management.
But
equal pay for identical job position, although a principle capable of revolutionary
potential in some circumstances, does not even begin to solve the problem of
formulating a wages policy. From a formal point of view, that principle merely
groups the workers into equivalence classes, without saying anything about the
relative salaries to be paid to the several classes. Paying all truck drivers
the same wage and all file clerks the same wage leaves undetermined which class
shall make more, and by how much.
Some
progress can be made by invoking Pareto comparability, assuming that there is
agreement on the dimensions along which different positions are to be compared.
If machine operating requires the same physical effort as truck driving, more
responsibility, at least as much dexterity, and more attentiveness, and if these
are the only qualities or characteristics of the work process which ought to
count in determining wage levels, then we can agree that machine operators
ought to make more than truck drivers.
But
now the old familiar indexing problems reappear! How shall we compare machine
operators with office workers, whose job demands greater literacy skills, less
physical effort, more independence of judgment, less manual dexterity, and
roughly the same degree of attentiveness? Once again, we must define an index
which allows us to map heterogeneous characteristics onto a one-dimensional
measure.
This
is by no means an issue of purely theoretical significance; you may be
interested to learn. In a number of large corporations in this country, top
management has found it necessary to develop a detailed policy of compensation
and raises which will possess some objective bureaucratic rationale and be
perceived as fair by the employees affected. In response to this need, a number
of management consultant firms, such as the Hay Company, have developed systems
of job evaluation designed to generate a unidimensional index, or numerical
measure, of the relative difficulty of the jobs performed by employees,
particularly at the lower and middle management levels.
Consider,
as an example, Sears, Roebucks, and Company, the great retail merchandising
firm. Sears employs thousands of men and women who occupy such job positions as
store manager, large appliances salesman, overhead fan buyer, truck driver,
cashier, and vice president in charge of the Middle Western states. These are
manifestly incommensurable jobs, requiring skills, talents, efforts and
personal characteristics that vary along many dimensions. Sears faces two
problems with regard to formulating a compensation policy in the face of this
diversity: First, at any given time, what wages or salary shall it pay each
position, and how shall it justify that compensation; and Second, how shall it
determine what relative raise to give each position annually?
Along
comes the Hay Company with a systematic answer. A middle level executive at
Sears - who, as it happens, is currently my brother-in-law - is assigned the
task of evaluating each of the hundreds of positions in the Sears system. This
executive travels around the country making on-site inspections. He assigns to
each job so many points for the amount of physical effort required, so many
points for the manual dexterity required, so many points for independence of judgment,
imagination, responsibility, direction of subordinates, and so forth, all
according to a complex process provided by Hay. He totals the assignments and
arrives thereby at the index of Hay points [as they are called] associated with
each position. The top management then decides how many dollars in compensation
will be paid per Hay point throughout the corporation, and a simple
multiplication gives the salary the Sears will pay to anyone occupying the
position. If the position of manager of a "B" store earns 5,134 Hay
points, and if Sears decides to pay eleven dollars a point, then any manager of
a "B" store will be paid 56,474 dollars.
As
for raises, Sears at the end of each year chooses an amount - let us say 87
cents - which it will pay per Hay point as a raise. Our store manager then
receives a raise of 4,466.58.
How
does the Hay Company, or my brother-in-law, decide, when implementing this
system, how much weight to assign to industry, initiative, independence, manual
dexterity, or the ability to operate a word processor? It should by now be
obvious that the answer cannot possibly be in terms of relative profitability
to the firm of its employees' possession of these various characteristics. If anyone
could actually ascertain directly such a measure of profitability, there would
be no need for the Hay system.
In
fact, as we might expect, the system embodies a number of normative or
evaluative presuppositions which are only thinly concealed by a putatively
impartial rationale. Head work is routinely assigned more Hay points than hand
work. Any position requiring its holder to direct or control the performance of
others is valued especially highly. It is not too simple to say that the Hay
Company has constructed an index designed to confirm and legitimate the greater
worth and hence higher salaries of the positions at the top of the executive
ladder, by assigning the greatest weight to whatever talents, skills, traits of
character, or modes of activity are in fact performed by those executives.
But
how could it be otherwise? During the Culture Revolution, the Chinese counterparts
of the Hay Company dictated an alternative set of evaluations, declaring manual
labor to be superior to mental labor, and so forth. The result may have been
morally superior - I leave that to your own judgment - but it was not, and
could not be, more 'objective.'
As
should be obvious, the existence in actual operation of practical systems of job
evaluation like that of the Hay Company constitutes a continuing source of rueful
embarrassment to conservative business men, like my brother-in-law, whose
politics incline them to look askance at the demands by organized women workers
for equal pay for comparable worth. One cannot operate the Hay system and claim
that the concept of comparable worth is economically meaningless without badly
fouling one's own nest! Nevertheless, the real thrust of my remarks is that my
brother-in-law is right. Any system for the indexing of incommensurable tasks
presupposes a set of normative or evaluative assumptions. Bringing those
assumptions to light does not permit us to eliminate them, for without them we
have no way of carrying out the indexing process.
Let
me tum, finally, to a third example drawn from a very different sphere, namely
Gerald Cohen's attempt in his important book, KARL MARX'S THEORY OF HISTORY, to
define an objective measure of the increase in productivity of an economy.
Cohen undertakes to defend a quite orthodox, uncomplicated version of Marx's
theory of historical materialism, one that many would call economistic,
technological, and determinist. After distinguishing, by some careful
conceptual analysis and textual exegesis, between the productive forces of an
economy and the social relations of production, Cohen summarizes his version of
Marx in two theses, which he labels the Development Thesis and the Primacy
Thesis.
The
development thesis states that 'the productive forces tend to develop
throughout history.' The primacy thesis offers a functional explanation of the
social relations of production in terms of their suitability for furthering the
development of the productive forces. The thesis states: 'The nature of the
production relations of a society is explained by the level of development of
its productive forces.' [Cohen, p.134] Cohen then goes on to give an original
and controversial defense of functional explanation in terms of what he calls
consequence laws.
Most
of the comment on Cohen's book, not surprisingly, has concentrated on the notion
of consequence laws, but there is, it seems to me, a prior problem
concerning the development thesis, a problem which, oddly enough, involves the
same issue of indexing that we have been examining in connection with Rawls'
work and the problem of wage determination and comparable worth.
At
the risk of appearing to have wandered away from Professor Buchanan's work into
a critique of Cohen, let me elaborate a bit the structure of Cohen's argument,
so that we can see precisely where and how an indexing problem arises.
At
this point, since the precise statement of Cohen's thesis will become rather
involved, I will ask you to refer to the handouts distributed at the beginning
of my remarks.
According
to Cohen, consequence laws have the following doubly hypothetical form: {see
handout, number 1}
IF it is the case that if an event of type
E were to occur at t1, then it would bring about an event of type F at t2
THEN an event of type E occurs at t3.
To
put the matter less technically and more provocatively, what explains the
occurrence of event E is the fact that if it were to occur, it would bring
about event F . Or, even more succinctly, E is explained by the fact that it is
functional for F.
Using
this formal structure we can now state Cohen's primacy thesis in proper
consequence law form, namely:
IF it is the case that if the
production relations conducive to the use and development of the productive
forces available in a society at that time come into being, then the productive
forces available at that time will be used and developed,
THEN the production relations conductive to
the use and development of the productive forces available in that society at
that time come into being.
To
defend his primacy thesis, Cohen must do four things. First, he must explain
what he means by 'productive forces available in a society' and ' production
relations of a society' with sufficient precision and clarity that we can tell
them apart, and also ascertain, for a given society, what productive forces are
available and what the production relations are in the society. Second, he must
explain what he means by the 'development' of productive forces, and specify
some way of telling as between two states of affairs in society, which
constitutes a higher development of the productive forces. Third, he must
defend explanation by consequence laws in general. And finally, he must offer
some evidence or argument in support of the particular consequence laws that
express the primacy thesis. It is in his attempt to meet the second of these
needs that Cohen runs of a foul of the indexing problem, in my judgment.
Cohen
defines an increase in productivity as an increase in the quantity of product
or output that can be produced with a given amount of direct labor. For
example, in a simple one- commodity economy that uses com and labor to produce
corn, an increase in productivity is an increase in the net output of com per
unit input of labor.
This
measure of productivity becomes problematical, as Cohen recognizes, as soon as
there are two or more commodities being produced, for a new technique might
permit us to produce more of the first commodity but less of the second, with a
given quantity of labor. Would this be an increase, a decrease, or no change in
productivity? Some technological innovations, of course, might enable us to
produce more of every commodity with the same labor, or at least more of some
and no less of others. In those cases we could appeal to a Pareto principle to
establish a rank ordering of relative productivity. But in the general case,
some way must be found to make what Cohen calls ' global productivity'
comparisons. Here is Cohen's solution:
Of course,
if everything producible at stage s1 is producible at stage s2,
and each thing at s2 in less time than s1, then we need no common
measure of the magnitude of products to claim that productivity is higher at s2.
But suppose forces at s2 outclasses those at s1 with respect to
some products, and are less powerful with respect to others. How can we then
make a global productivity comparison between s1 and s2?
In
certain instances of the type just identified comparison will still be possible
without a common measure of product size. Thus supposed that at both s1
and s2 twelve hours per day is the length of time each producer is able
to labor productively: marginal product is negative beyond that point. Imagine
that there are just three products, p, q, and r. At s1 it takes 3 hours
to produce a unit of p, 4 hours to produce a unit of q, and 5 hours to produce
a unit of r. At s2, it takes 2 hours to produce a unit of p, 3 hours to
produce a unit of q, and 6 hours to produce a unit of r. Then s2 is more
productive with respect to p and q, and less productive with respect to r.
Note, however, that only 11 of the 12 hours available at s2 are used up when
it produces one unit each of p, q, and r. Suppose the remaining hour were
allocated to producing r: then as long
as some r were produced in that hour, we should be able to say that s2
is globally more productive than s1, even though we have stated no
ratios between units of one product and units of any other. [Cohen, p.57]
But Cohen's argument is quit
incorrect. To see why, let us suppose that the technologies of s1 and s2,
are just as Cohen specifies, but that final demand for commodities p, q, and r
is different from that assumed by Cohen. In other words, let us suppose that
these societies, using these technologies, do not wish to produce one unit each
of p, q, and r.
Instead,
let final demand be .75 units of p, .5 units of q, and 1.5 units of r. In that
case, s1 is globally more productive that s2, for the desired
final demand requires 12 units of labor in s2 and only 11.75 units of labor
in s1.
Now
assume final demand to be one unit of p, 4/9 units of q, and 13/9 units of r.
In that case, s2 and s1 are equally globally productive, for the
desired final demand requires just 12 units of labor in each system.
But
'global productivity' is supposed to be an objective measure of the level of
development of productive forces, independent of consumer taste and final
demand. Thus Cohen's measure is unsatisfactory.
It
should be obvious that this result is perfectly general. For any two
technologies, one of which is more productive with respect to commodity i and
the other of which is more productive with respect with commodity j, there will
always be some final demand that makes the first technology globally more
productive, and yet a third final demand that makes them equally globally
productive.
In
fact, of course, we are presented here with exactly the same need for a
normative or evaluative principle as the basis for our indexing rule. Either we
must assume that the final demand manifested in the market by consumer behavior
has a moral sanction, so that consumer tastes will ultimately determine the
relative productivity of two stages of capitalist development
- an assumption which undermines any attempt to mount a critique of the
formation of consumer tastes- or else we must simply stipulate that some
commodities are worthier that others, and hence will count for more in the
index by which we measure productivity. For example, suppose that the advent of
industrialization and the decline of craft skills made it less costly in labor
hours to produce food, but more costly to produce hand-carved furniture. Is
that technological change an advance in productivity or not? It depends on our
moral evaluation of the relative importance of food and beautiful furniture.
Lest
we imagine that this is a purely theoretical quibble, let us reflect that
current debates about the effects of the economy on the environment are, from a
certain point of view, really arguments about the proper weights to use in an
index designed to measure increases in productivity.
I
hope it is clear from these three examples - Rawls, comparable worth, and Cohen
- both that the indexing problem arises repeatedly in theoretical and practical
contexts, and that it is always impossible to solve it in a value-neutral
manner. Here, as in so many other cases, supposedly objective formal methods of
analysis carry with them covert evaluation presuppositions which, if not
acknowledged, serve the ideological function of rationalizing particular
political or economic positions. I take this as one important example of the
general truth that politics cannot be reduced to rational administration, or
class conflict to impartial calculation.
Did your paper ever get published? This problem is, as you may know, widely recognized and discussed. (By the way, you've presented it here before:
ReplyDeletehttps://robertpaulwolff.blogspot.com/2013/01/the-indexing-problem-part-one.html )
This comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDeleteI just got around to reading this post today. I was not previously familiar with the terminology “indexing problem.” Prof. Wolff states: “Let us take a look, now, at a number of practical and theoretical contexts in which the indexing problem arises. My aim is to show you that in each case, a resolution of the problem requires a normative or prescriptive premise which must be exogenously introduced, as economists like to say.”
ReplyDeleteThis, I believe, parallels my discussion/debate with Prof. Zimmerman regarding the source/justification for moral precepts. I maintain that moral precepts cannot be proved, that a moral precept must be accepted as true without proof. Prof. Zimmerman maintains that claim is inadequate to justify believing in a moral precept (e.g., that slavery is morally wrong), and that it is possible to prove certain moral precepts based on rationality and the preclusion of contradictions. (This is my paraphrase of Prof. Zimmerman’s position, and he may claim that my paraphrase is erroneous.)
But if, as Prof. Wolff states, the indexing problem arises from exogenously introducing normative or prescriptive premises in order to justify one’s conclusions regarding the rectitude of social policies, and if those normative or prescriptive premises cannot themselves be proved, then they must be accepted as true and valid without proof – which is consistent with my position. In an earlier post, Prof. Wolff stated that he had given up the project of proving the validity of moral precepts as a futile pursuit. He was persuaded by a student to just decide “which side I was on.” But what does this mean, if not that the side you choose is based on one’s belief in moral precepts which are deemed true without proof?
Let’s say that my last statement is erroneous. Then the side we choose cannot be validated by proving the truth of the moral precepts which that side espouses. And they cannot be deemed true without proof. Where does that leave us? It leaves us nowhere, as Prof. Wolff later states about Prof. Rawls’ theory of justice:
“Although Rawls is aware of the problem of indexing, he glosses over them, admitting that we must ‘rely on our intuitive capacities.’ Nevertheless, he stands by the fundamental claim on which his entire philosophy rests, namely that his theory allows him ‘to replace moral judgments by those of rational prudence ….’ [THEORY OF JUSTICE p. 94]
“Rawls’ actual discussion of the indexing problem is arbitrary in the extreme. First he stipulates, with very little ground, that bargainers in the original position will choose to make rights and liberties lexically prior to all other primary goods. This has the effect of eliminating the need for an index that aggregates rights and liberties with the other primary goods, for lexical priority stipulates that any increase in rights and liberties, however small, will take precedence, for example, over any loss of wealth or income, however large.”
(Contineud)
But we can’t have it both ways, claiming on the one hand that our moral precepts are “intuitive” at the same time that we can justify them by invoking “rational prudence.” When we decide which side we are on, we presume that the side we choose is more correct, more valid, more ethical than the sides which oppose and are contrary to the side we choose. If this is not the case, why exert so much time and effort in seeking to advance the objectives of that side – even, in some cases, e.g., the Civil War, risking one’s life in support of that slave, i.e., opposing slavery?
ReplyDeleteYet every time that I have contended that our moral precepts – e.g., that the enslavement of other members of the species homo sapiens is per se morally wrong - are deemed valid without proof, I am accused of arbitrary authoritarianism. But if that is the case, then on what basis can one claim that the side one chooses to be on is more legitimate, more valid, more correct, more ethical than the sides we choose not to be on? And if we are unable to do that, what is the point of choosing sides other than to be arbitrary and authoritarian?
Correction:
ReplyDelete"risking one's life in support of that side, i.e., ...."
Marc
ReplyDeleteI wrote a long comment and lost it, but in brief your debate w D Zimmerman (whose position you mischaracterize) has nothing to do with this post (which is clear even on a cursory perusal of the post).
At least in ToJ as originally published, I think there is a tension between the claimed rational-choice aspect of justice as fairness and its role as a "framework designed to focus our moral sensibilities" (p.53). R's discussion of "reflective equilibrium" can be viewed as an effort to resolve the tension, though not everyone will think it succeeds.(Since I think you haven't read ToJ, this will seem cryptic to you, but so be it.)