Reflections on
REASON AND REFLECTIVE JUDGMENT
by
Paul Guyer
Robert Paul Wolff
Department of Philosophy
University of Massachusetts at
Amherst
Readers of the Critical Philosophy
are well aware - I find myself inclined to say painfully aware - of Kant's
penchant for issuing teleological judgments couched in the late scholastic
language of faculty psychology. The Critical Writings are filled with assertions
that Nature dictates such and such purposes for Productive Imagination, or that
Reason in its Practical Employment has an interest in this or that. At times,
Kant multiplies faculties of the mind like a mad phrenologist driven to feats
of hypostatization by an unusually bumpy skull.
Accompanying
these statements, which are legion, are dogmatic claims about the systematic
completeness of the Critical Philosophy, which, Kant tells us repeatedly, is
one of its distinguishing marks. Kant frequently construes the supposed
completeness of his system as an evidence of its truth, as when he says, in the
opening paragraph of the Transcendental Analytic, that 'The completeness and
articulation of [the system of pure concepts] can at the same time yield a criterion
of the correctness and genuineness of all its components.' [A6S=B90]
How,
as critical, philosophically engaged readers, ought we to interpret such claims
as these? How ought we to respond to them? At the outset, we can, I think,
assert with absolute confidence that Kant intended to make such claims,
believed them - at least in some sense of belief - and in fact set great store
by them. He would have reacted quite negatively to the suggestion that they
are, one and all, illegitimate echoes of a philosophical tradition which he,
more than any other single author, devastatingly and permanently discredited.
Nevertheless, that is patently the truth.
Consider,
for example, the following passage, taken from the second paragraph of The
Regulative Employment of the Ideas of Pure Reason, the portion of the CRITIQUE
from which Professor Guyer draws the preponderance of his citations.
Everything
that has its basis in the nature of our powers must be appropriate to, and
consistent with, their right employment - if only we can guard against a
certain misunderstanding and so can discover the proper direction of these
powers. We are entitled, therefore, to suppose that transcendental ideas have
their good, proper, and therefore immanent use, although when their meaning is
misunderstood, and they are taken for concepts of real things, they become
transcendent in their application and for that very reason can be delusive.
[A643=B671]
On
its face, this passage is doub1y absurd - first, by virtue of its invocation of
a quite groundless teleology, and second by its reliance on a classification of
powers or faculties of the mind for which Kant can offer no justification
whatsoever.
I
take it this harsh judgment would find widespread acceptance today, but it
might be worth recollecting just what is wrong with faculty psychology in its
teleological mode. The problem with discourse about faculties of the mind is
that we have no direct access to those faculties that would allow us to
identify them, differentiate them, and ascertain their normal, not to say their
appropriate, functions. I can get at the liver and the kidneys, either
by physical examination, by x-ray, or by autopsy. I can observe their
functioning, and draw conclusions about what they do in the body, and even - in
some not entirely indefensible sense - about what they are 'supposed' or
'intended' to do - this latter a harmless teleology that can be cashed either
by the medical notion of healthy functioning or by the evolutionary notion of
adaptability.
But
neither Kant nor we can obtain direct access to the Understanding, the
Imagination, Reason, Judgment, or Sensibility. Hence these titles can
legitimately be employed only as the empty names of the loci of certain
observable, or inferrable, activities, capacities, powers, or functions of the
mind. In the CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON, Kant almost always recognizes this fact.
When he observes, or infers, two activities of the mind whose structures
differ, he imputes them, appropriately to two distinct faculties. In some
passages, Kant explicitly recognizes that faculties are merely place-holders
for activities, as in the First Edition Deduction of the Pure Concepts of
Understanding, when he remarks that 'The unity of apperception in relation to
the synthesis of imagination is the understanding' - a statement which is
puzzling until we realize that it means: The Understanding is the empty name we
assign to whatever faculty of the mind it is that brings the manifold or
diversity of sense materials to the unity of apperception by means of the
synthetic activity which we arbitrarily impute to Imagination.
In
the central argument of the FIRST CRITIQUE, I can think of only one place where
Kant relies illegitimately on his faculty psychologizing - namely, in the
Metaphysical Deduction, when he argues, in backwards fashion, that the forms of
unity in synthesis must correspond to the forms of unity in judgment because
both judging and synthesizing are activities of the Understanding [A79=B105-6].
The
teleological utterances are equally unacceptable. Faculties of the mind, even
if we were able to locate them directly, could only be assigned purposes if we
imagined them to be the products of a purposeful creator.
My
own view is that we students of Kant must master this aspect of the Critical
Philosophy - must, in William S. Gilbert's immortal words, learn up all the
germs of the transcendental terms - that we must become entirely clear on the
role that a teleology of mental faculties plays in the CRITIQUE and the other
works of the Kantian corpus - and that we must then set it to one side as
virtually without philosophical merit or promise. In short, it has always
seemed to me that Kant's ebullient elaboration of the architectonic in all it
effulgent complexity has no more intellectual importance than Berkeley's
discourse on the virtues of tar water or Newton's fascination with astrology.
Professor
Guyer, with what I can only regard as heroic patience, has chosen to take a
different tack. Provoked - if that is the word - by Kant's decision to reassign
the ideal of systematicity from the faculty of pure theoretical reason to the
faculty of reflective judgment - a decision, one would have thought, as fraught
with philosophical significance as the telephone company's decision to reassign
its subscribers in the city of Worcester to the 508 area code - he undertakes,
by a painstaking review of Kant's remarks on systematicity, to extract from it
a philosophically interesting conclusion. It is a testimony to the acuteness of
his philosophical insight and the masterfulness of his scholarship that he is
moderately successful. When one is squeezing blood from a stone, a few drops
will suffice. One does not expect a transfusion.
The
central question, as Professor Guyer quite properly insists, is whether Kant
can produce some argument for the claim that complete systematicity of the
natural laws produced by the understanding is a condition of the possibility of
subjective consciousness. If Kant could plausibily maintain that we cannot even
be conscious unless our experience is sufficiently regular to ground the search
for systematic unity, then he could cash the teleological assertions about
tasks set for Reason by Nature in a genuinely interesting way.
Professor
Guyer and I disagree about whether Kant has something resembling a cogent
argument for the claim that subjective consciousness presupposes a synthesis
governed by the a priori rules labelled the categories. But we are, I take it,
in complete agreement that regardless of the status of the argument of the
Deduction, Kant cannot plausibly ground analogous claims for the Ideal of
systematic unity of the totality of our knowledge of nature. Nevertheless, as
is so often the case when one is puzzling over the Critical Philosophy, Kant
manages to raise philosophically interesting questions even in the least
promising precincts of his conceptual terrain. What is at stake in this issue
of systematicity?
As I
understand Professor Guyer, he thinks there are two things. The first is the
relation of the Causal Maxim, which Kant attempts to establish in the argument
culminating with the Second Analogy, to particular causal laws. The Second
Analogy asserts, in effect, that there must be valid causal laws to be found
which assert necessary connections among the events that constitute the
experienced world. But the proof - assuming for the moment that it is sound -
is not constructive. That is to say, at best it demonstrates the existence of
causal laws, but does not specify procedures for identifying them. Kant does
not, in fact, have much to say about the problems of justifying induction and
grounding scientific explanation that have occupied philosophers of science
during the past century and a half. Nor does he ever make clear in what way the
synthesizing activity of the understanding confers necessity on particular
scientific judgments. We know from the Introduction to the METAPHYSICAL
PRINCIPLES OF NATURAL SCIENCE that he thought all true science must be
mathematical in form, and that might encourage us to impute to Kant some
version of the story that scientific theories are uninterpreted formal systems
which, as a whole, have been set in relation to the world. Thus, the discussion
of systematicity might be construed as an attempt to specify the criteria by
which we can identify the correct structure of scientific laws.
If
that is in fact what Kant had in mind, then it seems to me not at all a bad
move on his part. The effort in the late nineteenth and early twentieth
centuries to produce a logic of induction that could justify individual causal
judgments by appeal to bodies of observational reports proved less promising,
in the end, than the alternative idea of treating formally organized systems of
scientific laws as the units to be justified or rejected.
The
second issue that Guyer sees Kant as raising is how to justify the heuristic or
methodological principles of scientific inquiry. Why ought we to construe the
unification of previously disjoint bodies of scientific laws as an advance in
our understanding of nature? Why is it a step forward for Newton to identify a single
set of premises from which both the laws of terrestrial motion and the laws of
celestial motion can be derived? Was it scientifically appropriate for Einstein
to devote the latter part of his life to a search for a unified field theory
uniting Relativity Theory with the theory of electro-magnetic phenomena, a
major goal of contemporary physics? And, more fundamentally still, what ground,
if any, do we have for supposing that such unifications are waiting to be
achieved?
Something
that looks curiously similar to the Kantian theme of conditions of the
possibility of experience has surfaced recently in the cosmological
speculations of such theoretical physicists as Stephen Hawking. In his recent
book, A BRIEF HISTORY OF TIME, Hawking repeatedly invokes what modern
physicists call the 'weak anthropic principle.' Hawking writes:
The weak
anthropic principle states that in a universe that is large or infinite in
space and/or time, the conditions necessary for the development of intelligent
life will be met only in certain regions that are limited in space and time,
The intelligent beings in these regions should therefore not be surprised if
they observe that their locality in the universe satisfies the conditions that
are necessary for their existence.
Somewhat
later, discussing what is now called string theory, Hawking again invokes the
anthropic principle to explain why only four of the ten or twenty-six
dimensions required by the theory are actually flattened out into what we call
space-time, rather than being curved in upon themselves into a space of very
tiny size. The answer, he suggests, lies in the laws governing gravitational
attractions between bodies. In three dimensions, the attraction between two
bodies is inversely proportional to the square of the distance between them. In
four dimensions, it is inversely proportional to the cube, in five dimensions
to the fourth power, and so forth.
'The significance of
this,' Hawking exp1ains, 'is that the orbits of planets, like the earth,
around the sun would be unstable: the least disturbance from a circular orbit
••• would result in the earth spiraling away from or into the sun. In fact, the
same behavior of gravity with distance in more than three space dimensions
means that the sun would not be able to exist in a stable state with pressure
balancing gravity. It would either fall apart or it would collapse to form a
black hole••• On a smaller scale, the electrical forces that cause the
electrons to orbit round the nucleus in an atom would behave in the same way as
gravitational forces. Thus the electrons would either escape from the atom
altogether or would spiral into the nucleus. In either case, one could not have
atoms as we know them.
It
seems clear then that life, at least as we know it, can exist only in regions
of space-time in which one time and three space dimensions are not curled up
small.
[Hawking,
pp. 164-5]
This talk of curled up
dimensions and black holes may seem a far cry from Kant's concerns with
systematicity, but perhaps we can see the anthropic principle as a descendant
of the Critical Philosophy's central theme, which is that reflections on the
conditions of the possibility of knowledge in general yield at least
conditionally a prior conclusions about the requisite structure of an
acceptable theory of nature.
8 comments:
"If time travel is possible, where are the tourists from the future?"
--S. Hawking
Without time travelers from the future, how could anyone prepare a large population for an escape from an E.L.E.?
All of the dinosaurs got wacked because no one from there future went back in time to help them. Then came the rise of the mammals. Hopefully, some people may help us from the future. The Rapture, an E.L.E., the Comet Wormwood of Revelation, the Seventh Rock of Zechariah, I believe they all have their ties to the same future human event.
Dear Michael,
perhaps they are in our midst. They may be adhering strictly to the prime directive of the space fleet as James T. Kirk and Jean Luc Picard once did.
Achim
"They may be adhering strictly to the prime directive."
Just like Gene Roddenberry, Elena Danaan & Dr. Michael Salla believe about alien species. Of course, both the latter's beliefs about benevolent aliens are more oppressive to the human race than Gene Roddenberry's story arc. Gene believed the Prime Directive is in effect until humans create a warp drive system. Miss Danaan says, however, that when a certain number of people reach a high enough frequency, then the benevolent alien governments will finally reveal themselves to Earth.
The belief of Miss Danaan's summarized is that you are supposed to look up to the sky in a safe place and say something like this:
"I am a human being and a member of this planet, this galaxy, and the Galactic Federation. As a free human being, I renounce all deals & treaties & contracts between this world's governments & any malevolent aliens & their governments. I am equal to you benevolent aliens & you are equal to me. No person rules over the other. I ask for your help, and I ask that you benevolent beings show yourselves to the entire world."
Elena Danaan is a great writer & storyteller, & her grand imagination makes her books come alive, but I eventually gave up reading her books because of several reasons like: she still believes the U.S. election was stolen, that Covid & mask wearing were made to keep the population down through fear mongering, & that some of her illustrations look like they're borrowed from some popular sci-fi shows. However, if Bob Frissell is the C.S. Lewis of New Age writings, then Elena Danaan can be considered the Tolkien of that genre. That's how diverse the universe is that she writes about.
However, whatever the truth is to that corny existential question: What the heck am I doing on this planet?, I take the road of pessimism & believe stuff will only get worse. However, as an opportunist I want to keep my eyes wide open. I am not content with that stupid song which is the summarization of existential 'bad faith' & therefore do no searching: "Que sera, sera: Whatever will be, will be..."
Where are the tourists from the future? I always assumed that they found the earth insufficiently interesting to warrant a visit during the Anthropocene, in particular since the extinction of the megafauna.--The philosopher and psychoanalyst Jonathan Lear's new book, Imagining the End: Mourning and Ethical Life opens with him recounting having heard a lecture on climate change, toward then end of which a young academic stands up and says "Let me tell you something: we will not be missed." Lear goes on to give an extraordinarily penetrating analysis of the remark, and ends up with thoughts on how it is bound up with the system of 'morality' (in Bernard Williams's conception), and how one might rather think and live outside of that debilitating system, in part by accepting mourning as a normal and indeed valuable part of human life.
The Anthropic Principle has had a long run, and was especially popular in the 1980s—along with fractals and chaos theory, and other hyper-sophisticated ideas that were supposed to change our view of how to understand the universe. Stephen Hawking (qua character) appeared several times on Bart Simpson. David Hume never got there, not even once, so far as I know, which is too bad. Hume made this wry comment back in 1748 about these sorts of thoughts: “Though the chain of arguments which conduct to it were ever so logical, there must arise a strong suspicion, if not an absolute assurance, that it has carried us quite beyond the reach of our faculties, when it leads to conclusions so extraordinary, and so remote from common life and experience. We are got into fairy land, long ere we have reached the last steps of our theory; and there we have no reason to trust our common methods of argument, or to think that our usual analogies and probabilities have any authority. Our line is too short to fathom such immense abysses."
"Our lineage is too short to fathom such monstrous depths."
Why not jump sometimes in the expectation that we will find solid ground where we land. Precisely because our "cognitive apparatus" is equipped only with a medium focal length, which can focus neither the immediately near, nor the all too far. One should only not forget after the jump that there was no bridge.
Post a Comment