THE INDEXING PROBLEM PART ONE
Professor
Buchanan has explicated for us, both in his paper today and in the book which
this session serves to celebrate, the limitations of the sorts of unanimity
partial orderings to which Vilfredo Pareto has given his name. In my remarks
today, I should like to explore some of the ways in which economists and
philosophers have sought to extend the scope of inter-systematic comparisons, and
to suggest reasons for believing that intersystemic comparisons must always
implicitly or otherwise embody some evaluative presuppositions. My thesis is
one more instance of a much broader theme, to which I have many times returned
in writing and teaching, namely that supposedly value-neutral models of formal
analysis usually contain powerful unacknowledged value assumptions which shape
their formal structure as well as their substantive content.
The
problem with unanimity partial orderings is that although they are transitive,
they are not complete. If everyone at our picnic prefers chocolate ice cream to
vanilla, then we can be sure that switching the dessert from vanilla to
chocolate will produce an increase in social welfare, assuming that everything
else remains unchanged, and that there are no externalities. Furthermore, if we
all prefer vanilla to pistachio as well, then the transitivity of individual
preference guarantees that we will all prefer chocolate to pistachio, and therefore
a switch of the dessert from pistachio to chocolate must increase social
welfare. But suppose some of us prefer
chocolate to vanilla and the rest prefer vanilla to chocolate. How shall we
evaluate the move from vanilla to chocolate, as a collective or group
decision?
Obviously,
it becomes necessary, at the very least, to ask how much the chocolate lovers prefer chocolate to vanilla, and the
vanilla lovers vanilla to chocolate. Some cardinal measure of preference
intensity, pleasure, welfare, preference priority, or even, a la Plato and
Mill, the relative objective value of the desire for chocolate versus the
desire for vanilla, will have to be invoked if we are to aggregate the
preferences or desires of the individuals at the picnic into a single group
ranking suitable for the making of a collective social choice. In short, we
shall have to define an index.
Bentham
assumed that pleasure is the only good, pain the only evil, and that pleasure
and pains, no matter whom they afflict, are intersubjectively comparable and
hence commensurable. These assumptions do not, of themselves, suffice for the
construction of an index, of course. It was still necessary for Bentham to
stipulate an aggregation rule or, in the modern jargon, a social welfare
function. His version of utilitarianism is just such a rule. We might state it
in modern terms something like this:
1. As between two policies, actions, or states of
affairs, A and B, if B provides to each individual in the society at least as
much net happiness as does A, and if there is at least one person to whom B
provides more net happiness than does A, then assign B a higher index number
than A.
2. As between two policies, actions, or states
of affairs, A and B, one of which provides more net happiness to some
individuals and the other of which provides more net happiness to other
individuals, measure the amounts of happiness accorded by each alternative to
each individual, using the same scale of measurement. Then [this, strictly
speaking, is the aggregation or indexing rule], following the rule ‘everybody
to count for one, nobody for more than one,’ add the quantities of net
happiness accorded by each alternative to all the individuals in the society,
and assign to A or B whichever has the larger sum.
We
are accustomed, in the light of the New Welfare Economics of the late
nineteenth and early twentieth century, to focus our attention on the phrase,
‘using the same scale of measurement,’ and then to invoke the supposed logical
impossibility of interpersonal comparisons of utility as a reason for rejecting
classical utilitarianism. But as Sen, Suppes, Harsanyi, and a number of other
theorists have shown us, there are ways of getting around the problems of
interpersonal comparisons which pose no greater philosophical difficulties than
the extreme solipsism that generates the problem in the first place. The real
problem is the purely normative clause, ‘everybody to count for one, nobody for
more than one.’ We can defend the assumption that the welfare of the society
consists in the arithmetic sum of the welfares of its individual members only
by positing the moral and political premise that all individuals are equally
important, or that each individual's happiness deserves to be given equal weight
in the social sum. And this premise simply
begs all of the questions of policy that utilitarianism was designed to
resolve.
Let
us take a look, now, at a number of practical and theoretical contexts in which
the indexing problem arises. My aim is to show you that in each case, a
resolution of the problem requires a normative or prescriptive premise which
must be exogenously introduced, as economists like to say.
My
first example is drawn from the work of John Raw1s. Raw1s, you will recall,
undertakes to extract a normative principle of distributive justice from
non-normative, or minimally normative, premises, by means of the conceptual
device of a bargaining game among rationally self-interested agents. In order
to avoid certain theoretical difficulties which stand in the way of his establishing
the principle that he wishes to promulgate, Raw1s introduces into his
theoretical construction a limitation on the knowledge available to the
participants in the bargaining game which he labels ‘the veil of ignorance.’
Unfortunately,
the veil of ignorance deprives the players in the game of so much information
that they no longer have any rational reason to care about its outcome. So
Raw1s is forced to re-equipped them with knowledge that they have coherent life–plans
whose fulfillment they are rationally committed to pursuing. But even this
information is insufficient, for what one wishes to bargain for depends on what
in particular one has chosen as a life plan. Hence Raw1s must add the notion of
primary goods, which is to say those things – ‘rights and liberties,
opportunities and powers, income and wealth’ – which, as he says ‘ a rational
man wants whatever else he wants.’ The idea is simply that no matter what life
plan one turns out to have chosen, possession of these primary goods will serve
to advance it.
But
now the indexing problem rears its head. Clearly, as between two principles of
distributive justice, A and B, if B promises at least as much of each primary
good as does A, and more of at least one, then B is to be preferred to A. But
suppose B promises more opportunity and less wealth, or greater income but less
power. How then shall the rational man behind the veil of ignorance choose? [I
say ‘rational man,’ because as a careful reader of A THEORY OF JUSTICE will
discover, Raw1s' world contains only men.] The answer is to construct an index
of primary goods. It is this number which the individuals in the original
position bargain over.
Although
Rawls is aware of the problems of indexing, he glosses over them, admitting
that we must ‘rely on our intuitive capacities.’ Nevertheless, he stands by the
fundamental claim on which his entire philosophy rests, namely that his theory
allows him’ to replace moral judgments by those of rational prudence…’ [THEORY
OF JUSTICE p. 94]
Raw1s’
actual discussion of the indexing problem is arbitrary in the extreme. First he
stipulates, with very little ground, that bargainers in the original position
will choose to make rights and liberties lexically prior to all other primary
goods. This has the effect of eliminating the need for an index that aggregates
rights and liberties with the other primary goods, for lexical priority
stipulates that any increase in rights and liberties, however small, will take
precedence, for example, over any loss of wealth or income, however large.
This
still leaves the problem of aggregating wealth and income with opportunities
and powers. Since this is manifestly impossible – how, for example, shall we
compare an increase of ten percent in the opportunity to pursue a medical
career as against a decrease in income of five thousand dollars a year? – Rawls
make yet another simplifying assumption. Reminding us that the Difference
Principle concerns itself primarily with the least well-off representative man,
Rawls simply asserts that the least advantaged tend to have both the least
wealth and income and the least powers and opportunities. In Short, Raw1s
assumes away any indexing problem at all.
But
clearly the issue is not so simple resolved. One of the major points of
controversy in modern social welfare policy concerns precisely the
relationship, in the lives of the least advantaged, of income or power. Radical
critics of current welfare practices have argued that transfer payments,
particularly payments in kind, have the effect of depriving the poor of social
and political power, and indeed may even have that as their purpose. Hence, as
between two social policies, one of which increases the income of the least
advantaged while making them impotent clients of the welfare bureaucracy, the
other of which increases economic or political power but at the cost of a
lowered income, it becomes a matter of substantive and evaluative social
philosophy which to espouse.
Rawls himself has
finally recognized the inescapably normative element in his notion of life
plans and primary goods. In a recent volume of essays titled UTILITARIANISM AND
BEYOND, edited by Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, Rawls returns to the
subject in an essay on ‘Social Unity and Primary Goods.’ In the following
passages, Rawls virtually acknowledges that the formation of an index of
primary goods presupposes normative constraints on what will count as an
acceptable life plan.
Imagine two persons,
one satisfied with a diet of milk, bread and beans, while the other is
distraught without expensive wines and exotic dishes. In short one has
expensive tastes, the other does not. If the two principles of justice are
understood in their simplest form (as I assume here), then we must say, the
objection runs, that with equal incomes both are equally satisfied. But this is
plainly not true…. The reply is that as moral persons citizens have some part
in forming and cultivating their final ends and preferences. It is not by
itself an objection to the use of primary goods that it does not accommodate
those with expensive tastes. One must argue in addition that it is
unreasonable, if not unjust, to hold such persons responsible for their preferences
and to require them to make out as best they can. But to argue this seems to
presuppose that citizens’ preferences are beyond their control as propensities
or cravings which simply happen.
And Rawls continues:
The idea of holding
citizens responsible for their ends is plausible, however, only on certain
assumptions. First, we must assume that citizens can regulate and revise their
ends and preferences in the light of expectations of primary goods. [And so
forth]
In
short we can hope to arrive at a usable definition of an index of primary goods,
only if we require that our prudentially self-interested bargainers constrain
their life-plans by considerations of fairness and, as Rawls says a bit later
in the same essay, the higher-order interests of moral persons.’ I think we can
fairly conclude that Rawls has failed, in his own words, ‘to replace moral
judgments by those of rational prudence.’
4 comments:
1. Interesting, but I cannot see that you have yet reached this conclusion: "....there is no social reality that is objective, value-neutral, and independent of our ideological representations. Because society is a collective human product, and because we unavoidably employ concepts in appropriating that social reality that are normatively encoded, society itself is inevitably mystified."
2. Are you assuming a connection between language and thought?
That is the subject of my book, MONEYBAGS MUST BE SO LUCKY.
This post led me to take down from the shelf my copy of A Theory of Justice (the original '71 edition, which I recently had bound as a hardcover because as a paperback it was falling apart).
I see what you're getting at with the indexing problem as it applies to primary goods, but I don't think this in itself is a fatal blow to Rawls's theory. Since the whole notion of primary goods rests on some normative presuppositions, bringing in more normative constraints on the people in the original position -- e.g., no life plans that involve expensive wines and exotic dishes every night -- might not matter that much. I do agree it conflicts with the statement about replacing moral judgments with rational prudence, but that's one statement in a long book. And I noted, in looking at this section of TJ just now, the conclusion of this section (p.95): "...the soundness of the theory of justice is shown as much in its consequences as in the prima facie acceptability of its premises. Indeed, these cannot be usefully separated and therefore the discussion of institutional questions, particularly in Part Two, which may seem at first unphilosophical, is in fact unavoidable."
Now that statement may admittedly raise some issues of its own, but for now I'll leave it there.
P.s. And the fact that Rawls seemed, in effect, to concede the point (in the later essay you cite) also suggests it's not crucial to his theory. If it were, he presumably wouldn't have conceded it.
Post a Comment