Today I shall begin to connect up
my exposition and reconstruction of Marx's economic analysis of capitalism with
his decision to write the opening chapters of Capital in highly charged, richly metaphorical language utterly
unlike that of either his predecessors or those who came after him [including,
of course, those who considered themselves his disciples and called themselves
Marxists.] Since this is going to take a
while, let me summarize the central idea at the outset so that you will find it
easier to follow.
Marx believes that capitalism is objectively mystified, that in fact its
mystifications are essential to its
continuing existence. These
mystifications go so deep into capitalist social reality that all of us, including
Marx and those who have learned from him, are infected with them,
beguiled by them, unable to get through the day without repeatedly reenacting
them and thus reinforcing them. It
follows that the only way in which Marx, or any of us, can simultaneously
anatomize those mystifications and also give them their proper weight and
significance in our understanding of capitalism is through the use of an ironic
voice. Merely understanding intellectually
the nature and origin of those mystifications is not sufficient to rid
ourselves of them, for they are not intellectual errors, nor are the result of
ignorance. Rather, they are necessary and inevitable so long as capitalism persists. Truly to be quits with them, Marx believes,
will require the overthrow of capitalism itself. [I happen to disagree with Marx that in a
socialist society mystification will disappear, but that is another matter --
at present I am trying to explain Marx, not criticize him.]Before returning to Capital, I am going to expand on the notion that a society can be objectively mystified. In this part of my story, I will be drawing on things I said in my essay, "Narrative Time: The Objectively Perspectival Structure of the Human World," which is archived on box.net and is available via the link at the top of this blog. I remind you that my purpose in writing this lengthy many-part essay is to weave together into a single coherent narrative ideas that I have put in print over the past thirty-five years and more.
According to the traditional Judeo-Christian-Muslim account, the universe is essentially a story told by God, with a beginning, a middle, and an end -- the Old Testament, New Testament, and Koran are the revealed versions of that story, suitable for human comprehension. [In The Chronicles of Narnia, a telling of the Christian story for children, the lion Aslan roars the world into existence -- an echo of the opening line of The Gospel According to John: "In the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God, and the Word was God."] Now, literary theory has a good deal to tell us about the structure and character of stories [or fictions, if you prefer the more pretentious locution.] If you think about novels, for example, you will immediately realize that they are written from a narrative point of view, which builds into the text a temporal structure and an anisotropic spatiality that define objectively significant times and places. In a novel there is a beginning and an end. A novel may privilege certain places as having a special significance that is in the space of the novel, not merely in the mind of the reader. For example [to choose one from very many], Edith Wharton's famous novella, Ethan Frome, has a frame structure, in which the narrator's story of Ethan and Mattie and the other characters begins as he lifts his foot to step over the threshold of the Frome home, and ends many pages later as his foot falls inside the doorway. Thresholds have a special significance in Wharton's novels that they do not have, say, in the novels of Austen or Dostoyevsky.
The crucial thing to note is that
because the world of a novel is created by the novelist's words, not
merely described by those words, the
fictional world actually has whatever properties the words of the novelist
ascribe to it. To choose another
example, in Dickens' novel Bleak House,
characters are in some passages described as having to walk all day to get from
one place [such as "Tom's all alone." a slum neighborhood] to
another. In other passages, they seem to
make the journey quickly. This is not an
error on Dickens' part [like Conan Doyle's inability to recall which leg Watson
took a bullet in during his stay in India].
Rather, the degree of the spatial separation is intended by Dickens as a
measure of the moral distance between the two parts of English society, and
that separation changes during the course of the novel.
Even names can have a creative
significance in a novel. Dickens plays
endlessly with the names of his characters as a way not of revealing but of constituting
their nature. If an historian labels the
economic, social, and technological changes of the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries an "industrial revolution," she is making a claim about
their nature, asserting, we may suppose, that in the scope and depth of their effects
they produced as a great a change in Europe as the overthrow of the British and
French monarchies. But when Dickens
names a group of greedy poor relations The Pockets, he is literally creating
their distinctive trait in the act of naming.
Now the physical world was not
created by God, so nature is not a story with a narrative structure. There is, however, another world that is not
natural but rather created -- the social world.
Society is not, of course, the product of a single purposeful
individual. It is rather the product of
countless purposeful individuals whose choices, desires, habits, expectations,
understandings, misunderstandings, fantasies, and concepts create and recreate
-- or produce and reproduce, to use the economic terms -- the social realm. At any moment we wish to choose in the
evolution of society, individuals experience social reality as objectively
real, independent of their wills, given in just the way that the natural world
is given. No one is capable of stepping
completely outside of the social world he or she has encountered at birth and
in the process of becoming a fully developed human being.
This simple truth, so often
denied, is central to my story, and needs to be elaborated upon. Some philosophers in the Western tradition
have seemed to suggest that at birth the infant is a tiny rational agent not
yet possessed of useful information about the world and a control of its bodily
functions. But that, we now know, is
absurd. It takes a long time [and a
village, according to some political aspirants] for the infant to develop into
a coherent person, and in the course of that development, each infant
internalizes some particular way of interacting with the world, managing its
drives and fantasies, deferring gratifications, and coming to terms with its
sexuality, all of which makes the child a twenty-first century working class
Indian, an eighteenth century aristocratic Frenchman, a Roman slave, a Chinese
peasant, a Boston Irish ward heeler.
Even such seemingly "natural" matters as how one walks, sits,
or stands turn out to be culturally internalized and reenacted by the
individual. Those who rebel against
social norms and strive to create their own ways of being, free the dead hand
of the past, end up rebelling in ways that are immediately recognizable as shaped
by the culture from which the rebel has declared his or her independence.
[Those wishing to pursue this in
more depth might find it interesting to read Michael Oakeshott's great essay,
'Rationalism in Politics," in the book of the same title, or Erik
Erikson's seminal work, Childhood and
Society, or -- not at all in their class -- my tutorials on The Thought of
Sigmund Freud and How to Study Society, archived on box.net.]
Tomorrow, we shall see how Marx
engages with these ideas.
4 comments:
Fascinating to say the least. I'm especially intrigued by the role assigned to irony as the singular (?) means by which the relationship between appearance and reality is to be or can be made apparent. The question in my mind at this point is this: if capitalism is "objectively mystified," how is it possible to have a "real audience?" Who's in the know?
I will be patient and await further installments.
I agree that rebellion is necessarily conditioned by its given antecedents. However, that it is always "immediately recognizable" as such is less clear to me. For, those remaining within the status quo tend to lack the requisite insight, while the more significant the rebellion, the less can the rebels grasp its full consequences, which may extend for centuries.
Jerry, the question you ask is a very important one, and the reason for the extended example from catholicism. because we are complex persons, not simple, we can be, under the right circumstances, both the apparent and the real audience for an ironic communication. No one throughly implicated in the commodification of capitalist society can free himself or herself from it completely. hence a part of me is always the apparent asudience.
Which is deeper, the Marxist analysis or the Freudian one in which we are always at least partially beset by the illusions "we" ourselves create? The ironic position that we occupy is not of our own making. Whether the forces are economic or broadly psychological the one thing that is certain is that it is only through often painful dialogue that we reach a position tentatively outside of whatever cave we find ourselves in.
Many thanks as always for your prose, your commitment to philosophy, and to your intellectual generosity in allowing us to eavesdrop on your thinking!
Post a Comment