Marx does not present his explanation for the
existence of profit in the form of equations.
Instead, he poses a question that, he believes, has stumped his predecessors,
and then presents his theoretical discovery as its solution. The problem is that even in the ideal case in
which commodities of all sorts exchange in exact proportion to the quantities
of labor directly and indirectly required for their production, which is to say
exchange at their values, the capitalist
somehow manages to exit from each cycle of production and exchange richer than
he was before. Here is the way Marx
poses the problem in the final paragraph of Chapter V, "Contradictions in
the General Formula of Capital."
Our friend, Moneybags, who
as yet is only an embryo capitalist, must buy his commodities at their value,
must sell them at their value, and yet at the end of the process must withdraw
more value from circulation than he threw into it at starting. His development into a full-grown capitalist
must take place both within the sphere of circulation and without it. These are the conditions of the problem. Hic Rhodus, hic salta."
A few words about the ironic use of "Moneybags,"
which is an odd term to find an a work of theoretical economics. The German is geldbesitzer, whose literal translation would be "possessor of
money." I use the old translation
of Capital prepared from the 1887
Third Edition, after Marx's death, by Edward Aveling [the partner, but never
actually the husband, of Marx's daughter] and Samuel Moore, and personally
edited and overseen by Engels himself.
To nineteen century English readers, "moneybags" would have
conjured up the cartoons of political caricaturists like Thomas Nast -- a drawing
of a fat little man in a top hat and cutaway coat with a dollar or pound sign
on his vest. Those of you who have
played the original version of the board game Monopoly will recall this character on the "Get out of jail
free" card. The translation, which
plays on the etymology of geldbesitzer
as someone sitting on a bag of money, perfectly captures Marx's mocking tone.
The Latin tag at the end of the paragraph is
yet another instance of Marx's rich, multi-lingual array of cultural references
and invocations. It refers to a story
about a man in ancient Rome who bragged of having made an extraordinary athletic
broad jump when in Rhodes. His friends,
unimpressed, challenged him to reproduce the feat, saying, "Rhodes is
right here. Jump here!" Hic
Rhodus, hic salta. Marx's habit of
alluding in this way to the broad, deep range of literature in the Graeco-Roman
Judeo-Christian tradition is no mere literary tic or bit of showing-off. It is his way of situating his economic
theories in the context of Western Civilization, so that his readers will
understand that he seeks to expose not merely the workings of the marketplace
but the inner logic of the ideological rationalizations that have been
elaborated to mystify and justify exploitation and oppression. But more of that later.
Immediately in the first paragraph of the next
chapter, "The Buying and Selling of Labour-Power," Marx presents his
solution to the puzzle, Whence profit?
His solution, and the capstone to his entire critique of capitalism, is
the distinction between labor and labor power -- between the work the laborer
does for his wages, and the laborer's capacity for labor, which is what he
rents out to the employer on an hourly, daily, or weekly contract.
Moneybags must be so
lucky as to find, within the sphere of circulation, in the market, a commodity,
whose use-value possesses the peculiar property of being a source of value,
whose actual consumption, therefore, is itself an embodiment of labour, and,
consequently, a creation of value. The
possessor of money does find on the market such a special commodity in capacity
for labour or labour-power.
In short, the capitalist pays for the labor of
his worker a price equal to its cost of production, which is to say an amount
in money just capable of paying for the food, clothing, and shelter that the
worker must consume to produce his or her salable commodity, which is
labor-power. Thus the worker is paid no
more and no less than is paid to the coal seller, cloth seller, linen seller,
and machine seller, each of whom sells his goods for a price exactly equal in
value to the labor embodied in them.
Suppose, Marx says, by way of illustration,
that the worker's necessaries require the expenditure of six hours of labor,
directly or indirectly, somewhere in the economy, for their production. If the capitalist can get the worker to labor
for more than six hours a day -- for twelve hours, let us say, which was in
Marx's day the typical workday for a day laborer -- then the extra labor, the surplus labor, produced by the worker
and embodied in the commodities she produces, will confer on those commodities
a surplus value, which the capitalist will pocket when he exits the sphere of
production and enters the sphere of circulation to sell his goods. This difference between the value embodied in
labor and the cost of production of labor-power is, Marx says, the origin of
profit. Notice, by the way, as the
theologians, jurists, and philosophers supported by the largesse of the
capitalist will be sure to explain, that the capitalist in thus enriching
himself is not cheating either his workers or his customers. To his workers, the capitalist pays exactly
the value of the labor-power he rents from them, namely an amount equal to the
value embodied in that labor-power. And
from his customers the capitalist demands only so much money as equals the
value contained in what they are buying.
It is for this reason that the capitalist can go to church each Sunday
with a clear conscience, comfortable in the knowledge that he has fulfilled to
the last jot and tittle the strictures of bourgeois justice. The little numerical example we carried
through demonstrated with arithmetic rigor the correctness of Marx's claim.
If we now look a little more closely at this argument, we
will discover that it does not actually prove what it is intended to
prove. Marx seeks to demonstrate that profit is merely
the monetary expression of the extra or surplus labor embodied by the workers
in the produced output in the course of the production process. According to him, the value of the corn and
iron, in our little model, is merely labor embodied in the corn and iron inputs
and transferred from them to the output, without augmentation, during the
production process. But the workers,
when they labor in the factories or on the farms, create new value, for value
is simply embodied labor. Now, we can
distinguish between the worker's capacity to labor, or labor-power, and the
actual labor performed by the worker. It
is the worker's capacity for labor, or labor power, that the capitalist rents
when he sets the worker to work in the factory or on the farm. And the difference between the value of that labor-power and the amount
of new labor provided by the worker, that surplus
labor, or surplus value [since
value simply is embodied labor], is exactly, quantitatively, the capitalist's
profit.
But look more closely at the labor value equations whose
solution yielded the values, in our model, of λc, λi, and λb.
Considered purely formally, without regard to the story Marx is telling
us, what distinguishes labor from corn, iron, and books in those equations is
the fact that the labor inputs are entered at full value -- 100 units of labor
in the corn sector is entered as 100 units, where as all the other inputs -- of
corn and iron -- are discounted by their labor values.
Suppose now we ask a question that neither Smith, Ricardo,
nor Marx ever thought to ask: How much
corn does it take, directly and indirectly, to produce one unit of iron, books,
or labor? In short, what is the corn value of iron, books, or labor?
CORN VALUE?? What on
earth am I talking about? There is no
such thing as "corn value!"
["There is no crying in baseball."] Labor
is the substance of value, not corn [or iron, for that matter.] But the claim that labor is the substance of
value was not based on some sort of a
priori intuition or philosophical argument.
That claim was supposed by Smith and Ricardo and by Marx as well to be
validated by the success that such a claim had in explaining the existence of
natural prices [or, in modern jargon, equilibrium prices] in the
marketplace.
Who would be crazy enough to ask such a question? Well, hem hem, the answer is, I would. I asked just this question in my 1981
article, "A Critique and Reinterpretation of Marx's Labor Theory of
Value." How would we even go about
calculating corn values? The answer is
quite simple. Just set up equations on
the basis of the Corn-Iron-Books model above, but introduce a new set of
variables for corn values. [Greek does
not have a letter "c," so we need to use the Greek letter k, or κ.] We use the same subscripts, but now κi will stand
for "the quantity of corn directly and indirectly required for the
production of one unit of iron."
And we will, of course, have to introduce a variable κl to
represent the quantity of corn directly and indirectly required for the
production of one unit of labor. The
variable κc
in this set of equations will stand for the amount of corn directly and
indirectly required to produce one unit of corn.
It should be intuitively obvious that every single
conclusion we drew about labor values and surplus labor value and profits can
be reproduced for corn values and surplus corn value and profits, without the
need to introduce some sort of distinction between corn and corn power. If that is not intuitively obvious, then take
it from me. I proved it [and I
reproduced the proof in the Appendix to my book Understanding Marx.] The
difference between the corn-value of a bushel of corn and a bushel of corn will
be precisely the surplus corn value extracted from the corn inputs, and sure
enough, the total surplus corn value extracted from the corn inputs will
exactly equal the corn value of the physical surplus of labor, iron, and books.
How can we be sure that the corn value of corn will be less
than 1, thus creating surplus corn value?
Answer: So long as there is a
physical surplus of some sort in the system, it is mathematically necessary
that the quantity of any basic commodity required to produce one unit of that
same commodity will be less than 1.
[Basic commodities are commodities that are directly or indirectly
required for the production of every commodity in the system.]
In short, by constructing our equations for the purpose, we
can show that corn is exploited, or that iron is exploited, or that any other
basic commodity is exploited. There is
nothing special about labor. However, if
we want corn values to be proportional to prices, we will have to construct a
system that exhibits equal corn-organic composition of capital. Since the model we have been working with was
carefully constructed by me to exhibit equal labor-organic composition of
capital, not equal corn-organic composition of capital, it won't do.
So Marx was just plain wrong about the secret of the
extraction of profit from the workers. BUT HE WAS NOT WRONG THAT PROFIT ORIGINATES
IN THE EXPLOITATION OF THE WORKING CLASS.
He just did not have the correct analysis. In fact, Marx knew perfectly well how and why
it is that workers come to be exploited, and he told us at great length in Capital.
So what is the
correct analysis? Funny you should
ask. I will tell you tomorrow.
7 comments:
Damn, I really hate to keep stressing this point, but so many of your criticisms against Marx are addressed by Andrew Kliman and Alan Freeman...All this talk about "marx couldn't have known this" due to various mathematical tools he was lacking, are refuted.
As a Marxist, you kind of have a duty to read their work...
Damn, I really hate to keep stressing this point, but so many of your criticisms against Marx are addressed by Andrew Kliman and Alan Freeman...All this talk about "marx couldn't have known this" due to various mathematical tools he was lacking, are refuted.
As a Marxist, you kind of have a duty to read their work...
Chris, I will take a look at Kliman when I get around to it, but I think I already know what his line is. Notice that I do NOT say that Marx contradicts himself. Quite to the contrary. And although I trhink the Labor theory of Value is the wrong way to capture Marx's correct insights into capitalism, as I shall explain shortly, I am as enthusiastic in my admoration for Marx as I imagine Kliman is. Just be patient.
I think I see what you're slowly driving at with this series, Professor Wolff (though I'm prepared to be wrong, of course). This quotation from Kalecki may get at the same point:
"The tragedy of investment is that it causes crisis because it is useful. Doubtless many people will consider this paradoxical. But it is not the theory which is paradoxical, but its subject—the capitalist economy."
That is indeed a part of it. Lord, it is taking me forever, but it is a complicated idea, and requires a very great deal of explaining.
Finally! For me, another puzzling question answered - while Marx's notion of exploitation vindicated. (Blogs as illuminating instruction; take note Mr. Sullivan.)
Prof.
I see that, in addition to a good sense of humor, you also have a penchant for mischief...
Post a Comment