The model itself can
be found in the essay that I have deposited in box.net. For those of you who choose not to look at it
there, suffice it to say that the central idea is to model the workers'
production of labor as an industry, on a par with all the others, in which
however there is a rate of return that is distinct from the rate of return in
the other industries of the economy.
Because the workers cannot shift their "capital" into other
lines of production, they are unable to capture a portion of the higher rate of
return being offered there. Hence their
rate of return, if indeed it rises above zero [which is to say, if the workers
can manage to do better than mere subsistence], will always be lower than the
society wide profit rate. Analytically,
what this means is that whereas they are compelled to sell their
"product" [their labor] at its labor value, they must buy their inputs
[their food, clothing, and shelter] at prices above their labor value. This has the effect of transferring away to the
producers of those wage goods a portion of the labor value produced by the
workers. Not surprisingly, it is easy to
show that the quantity of value this transferred away from the workers by
forcing them to pay higher prices just exactly equals the value of the physical
surplus generated in the economy and also exactly equals the money profit
earned by the capitalists. If this does
not seem intuitively obvious, reflect on the fact that in an economy hell-bent
on expansion ["Accumulate, accumulate. That is Moses and the
Prophets."], the consumers of final goods are the workers. The consumption of the parsimonious, pious,
Puritanical capitalists is negligible -- there are, after all, very few of them
relative to the workers.
Let us stand off a bit
from the detail of the model and reflect on what our analysis has taught us.
According to Marx, the central craziness (Verrücktheit, he calls it) of
capitalism is the fact that the capacity to labor, to transform nature purposefully
and artfully in the service of human need, is treated in the marketplace as a
commodity. This absurdity has its historical roots in the separation of the
working class from the means of production. It is, under capitalism, the root
and source of exploitation, which, technically speaking, is the extraction from
a factor of production of more value than is embodied or contained within it.
Thus far, I follow
Marx completely. His insight is, in my judgment, correct, as are the essential
elements of his historical account. (The two other fundamental crazinesses of
capitalism, to which Marx devotes equal attention, are the emergence of money
and capital as objectively real social forms, and the existence of internal
crises of over-production. I cannot
spend as much space here as would be required to deal with those
"contradictions," although a fully adequate reconstruction of Marx's
political economy must deal with both in such a manner as to establish their
relationship to the treatment of labor power as a commodity.)
Marx locates exploitation
in the sphere of production, not in the sphere of circulation (behind the factory
door, not in the sunlit market), and identifies exploitation with the
extraction of surplus labor-time from the workers. His principal analytic
maneuver is the distinction between labor and labor power, and his most
powerful justification for the labor theory of value is its success, in
conjunction with that distinction, in identifying the precise source and
quantity of surplus value extracted by the capitalists in the process of production.
Marx's analysis of exploitation is incorrect, as we have seen. But his central
insight is perfectly correct: the root of exploitation, and the source of
surplus value, is the treatment of labor power as a produced commodity.
However, exploitation
does not take place in the sphere of production; nor does it take place in the
sphere of circulation. Rather, the extraction of the surplus from the workers
takes place in the interaction between the spheres of production and
circulation. To be precise, the extraction of the surplus comes about through
the fact that the workers are forced to sell their product (labor power) at its
labor value, but must purchase the non-labor inputs into their production
process (that is, their food, clothing, and shelter) at prices driven above
their values. Capitalists are able to earn the economy-wide rate of profit
because they are able to shift their capital into or out of lines of production
according to whether the short-term, or market profit-rate is above or below
the natural or economy-wide profit rate. The anomalous status of workers
prohibits them from shifting their "capital" about in search of a
higher rate of return, and the existence of a reserve army of the unemployed
effectively drives the rate of return in the labor-producing industry down to
zero.
In Capital, Marx
represents the workers, with bitter irony, as suffering exploitation because of
the sheer metaphysical accident that their product happens to be capable of
creating exchange value when it is consumed as a use value. In short, Marx says
that the workers can be exploited because labor is the substance of value. The
truth, not surprisingly, is the exact opposite: labor is the substance of
value because the workers can be exploited!
To put the same point
somewhat differently, the distinguishing logical feature of labor in a formal
model of a capitalist economy is not that it must be chosen as numeraire, for
that is simply false; nor that commodities, at their natural prices, exchange
in proportion to the quantities of labor directly or indirectly required for
their production, for that too is false. The distinguishing logical feature of
labor in a capitalist economy is that the industry producing it does not in
general earn the uniform rate of return on the value of capital invested. Any
notational system which contains within it enough in the way of formal
differentiation to permit an adequate representation of the formal structure of
capitalism will preserve this logical peculiarity. It makes no difference
whether we use the Greek letter lambda to signify that we are representing
labor. What matters is that the logical, or formal, relationships between labor
and the other elements of a capitalist economy be modeled in our formal system.
So long as this condition is met, the formal structure we set out will be
adequate to serve as the basis for an analysis of exploitation consonant with
Marx's central insights.
There is a very great
deal more to be said about the implications of this analysis, of course, and I
simply cannot impose upon my little band of readers to that extent. But it is worth saying a few things to
connect this analysis with the situation we confront in contemporary capitalist
society, which differs in important respects from the world Marx was writing
about.
Marx treated all labor
as essentially interchangeable [referring on occasion to skilled labor as
simply a "multiple" of unskilled labor.] This makes it possible for us to model
capitalism as having a single labor-producing sector with a single "rate
of return," ρ. He believed that
historical forces were inexorably destroying the traditions of skilled labor,
replacing it with semi-skilled machine tending labor. Indeed, this homogenization of labor, he
thought, was the condition for the development of a unified proletariat. It was, on the side of labor, the
counterpart, he thought, to the progressive absorption of small capitals into
big capitals, leading eventually to a confrontation between big capital and
organized labor.
But the reality, one
hundred fifty years after the publication of Capital, is different. We
see a segmented labor sector with seemingly permanent distinctions between
unskilled, semi-skilled, and skilled labor.
To model this situation properly we would need to introduce a number of
distinct labor producing sectors, each with its own capital requirements [most
notably in the form of education, resulting in what Gary Becker called human
capital.] As Samuel Bowles and Herb
Gintis showed many years ago in a fascinating journal article, this situation
leads to what they called "relative exploitation." That is to say, capital exploits labor, and
skilled labor relatively exploits unskilled labor.
All of this, in a quite
natural way, can be understood as resulting from the different degrees of
freedom with which workers in one or another of these "labor
industries" can shift their "capital" so as to capture a larger
share of the surplus. Intuitively, an
unskilled worker who manages to acquire some post-secondary education acquires
"capital" that allows her to shift to a different line of labor
production without "cashing in" her body by dying. She has capital other than her body that can actually
be transferred to a different line of labor production. It remains the case that she is exploited,
and hence that the return that she earns on her capital is lower than the
return on money capital earned by capitalists.
But she does manage to appropriate some portion of the social surplus,
which enables her to live markedly better than those in the unskilled labor
sector. Not surprisingly, once she has
made that transition, she does not retain either a subjective sense of
solidarity with her former comrades nor an objective community of interest that
could serve as the basis for the successful organizing of a united labor front.
By means of a formal
analysis, I have managed to introduce the odd notion of a formal model capturing
and encapsulating the mystification and false consciousness of capitalist
economy and society. This takes us part
of the way to an explanation of Marx's highly unusual language in Capital, the puzzle with which I
started, but to complete my explanation, I must now spend some time talking
directly about language. So tomorrow we
take leave for a bit of economics and linear algebra and turn to English
Metaphysical Poetry of the seventeenth century.
You humanists can breathe a sigh of relief.
8 comments:
So just how does one access your box.net files or account?
Not that I quite agree with your account of Marx, but doesn't it amount to saying that the "exploitation" of labor is a form of economic rent extraction?
you access it using the link at the top of the page on my blog. It is, in a sense, the inverse of rent
Ah! At the top of my computer screen it says "this gadget is in error". So it's my own fault, for not having kept up with the latest advances in computer software, with sufficient tender loving care for my computer's innards. Oh well.
I'm not understanding just why you think that, given your criticism that formally any other numaire would do in the place of labor, a purely formal rather than "substantive' specification is require to distinguish the role of labor. Why not just say that, at least until our robot overlords fully take over, labor is the only "factor of production' possessing the properties of cognizant sentience and intentionality? Hence labor is the only active ingredient that can bring the other factors together, in relation to the expense of effortful activity and need.
At any rate, here is a paper by a mainstream economist telling his fellow mainstream economists that they're all wet about Marx:
The Transformation of Values: What Marx "Really" Meant (An Interpretation)
William J. Baumol
Journal of Economic Literature
Vol. 12, No. 1 (Mar., 1974), pp. 51-62
Published by: American Economic Association
Article Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2721866
It's the same fellow who earned his "immortality" in the econ literature with his paper on "Baumol's cost disease". And, indeed, your account resembles a "cost disease" account, more than I what I would take to be Marx'.
In response to your first comment, which is in the form a question, my answer is, Because what you say about consciousness and intentionality, which is certainly true, is not modelled in the formal analysis of the economy, and hence has the status of a commentary, as it were, rather than an analysis of the structure of capitalism itself.
Moving on, Alan freeman's rather punchy paper "If they're so rich, why ain't they smart?" is a good intro to the temporal single system account of the "transformation problem". It ends with a brief discussion of Sraffa and "physicalism", which he sees as valid as an internal criticism of marginalism, but, when stood on its own, it reproduces in its own way the problems of marginalism.
Prof.
Other opinions notwithstanding, I find your treatment of this matter quite interesting and, as it allows for differential levels of remuneration (as I previously commented somewhere else), rings true to experience.
Indeed, this seems like a way to represent something quite like the Engels/Lenin labour aristocracy into play.
In actual practice, beyond the more theoretical finer points, it seems compatible with Marx's own main conclusions.
Is all this contained in your Understanding Marx book? And could you provide further details about the Bowles and Gintis article?
Post a Comment