This
will be a lengthy
meditation on such concepts as racism [and sexism, elitism, ageism, classism,
etc. etc], which I believe to be much more complicated and problematic than the discussion in class suggests.
But first: Mea culpa,
mea culpa, mea maxima culpa! Bob is absolutely correct. Exodus, Chapter
12, Verses 35-36: "And the children of Israel did according to the word of Moses;
and they borrowed
of the Egyptians jewels of silver, and jewels of gold, and raiment: And the Lord gave the people
favour in the sight of the Egyptians, so that they lent unto them such things as they required. And they spoiled the Egyptians." So much for relying on a memory
corrupted by Cecil
B. De Mille!
Now, let us turn to more serious matters
[though what could be more serious than the Exodus
out of Egypt, I don't know.] I will
develop my analysis in reference to the term, "racism," and will leave it to you to think through analogous analyses for other terms. My aim here, as throughout the course, is two-fold: to get you to think historically, and to get you to think more complicatedly. I want you to learn to bring
to bear on highly charged,
politically highly inflected
matters the care, precision, and analytic skill that you learn to use when writing about arcane matters
of epistemology, metaphysics, logic, or language.
We start with the state of affairs that existed -in late medieval
Europe, or in ancient Greece and Rome, or in the United States before the Civil
War, or in South Africa
today. A number of different legal statuses are explicitly defined
by statutory or customary law, to which are attached
differential benefits and burdens. In the twelfth
century, in what is now France,
if you are a member of the regular clergy [i.e., a member of an order that lives
by a rule- is "regular"- such as the Benedictines], legal questions concerning your property, or damages you are accused of having inflicted on another, and so forth, are heard in an ecclesiastical court.
If you are a peer of the realm, such matters will be heard by one of the courts of the provincial Estates. If you are a freedman,
your case will be heard in a court presided
over by the lord who rules the domain in which you live. If you are unfree - a serf, i.e. "servile"- you will not have the right to have your cause
weighed by a court of law.
The
taxes you owe, the military
service you owe, the labor
services you must render, whether you may marry and whom, and many other things as well, will be determined by your legal status. Similarly, in classical Greece
and Rome or ante-bellum United States, such matters
will be determined by whether
you are slave
or free. In the
United States, but notin Greece or Rome, all those who are slaves are thought of as belonging to a single
race of the human species
- although that is a concept that is
not in fact as old as the institution of slavery even in the United States.
In South Africa, there is a legal system of racial classification on which
rests the right of individuals to reside, own property, vote, marry, travel,
hold jobs, and so forth.
The absolutely crucial thing to get clear at the start is that, at this point in the historical development of what will eventually become the concept
of racism, we are talking about legal
statuses, not feelings, attitudes, theories, prejudices, or unacknowledged limitations of perception. In South Africa,
for example, each year there are a hundred or more court cases in which individuals are officially reclassified from one racial
group to another. [It is also the case, on occasion, that members of the same immediate family
are assigned to different racial categories.] Now, there is, of course,
a tricky theoretical question whether such legal statuses are descriptive or ascriptive, and my own view
is that they are ascriptive. Briefly, what is at issue is the question
whether the law describes someone's status
- discovering it, when operating
correctly, or making a mistake when not - or alternatively ascribes a status to an individual by means of a legal procedure. On the ascriptive interpretation, for example,
the statement that A killed B is, or purports
to be descriptive, but the statement that A
is a
murderer is ascriptive. On this view, there is no meaning
to the question, "Is A really a murderer, even though the courts have failed to find him guilty?" any more than there is to the question, romantic
though it might sound [to some, but not to Lisa], "Are A and B really
married, even though they have never gone through a marriage ceremony?"
Accompanying
the differential legal statuses may be some rationale or justification that appeals to supposed innate differences among individuals assigned to different statuses
- such as a theory of racial, ethnic, religious, or gender differences. For example, medieval Muslim law treats "people of the book"- i.e., Jews and Christians- differently from infidels, on the ground,
supposedly, that Jews and Christians acknowledge portions of the revelation
that Muslims drum to have come from Allah. And the Greeks
deprecated "barbarians" - i.e., those who did not speak Greek, and hence sounded,
to the Greeks, as though
they were saying "bar bar bar." But in a system of legally ascribed
statuses, how one is treated
is a function of one's legal status,
regardless of what others feel or think about one.
The first step in any liberation struggle
is, inevitably, the attempt to remove the legal disabilities and instead establish
it as a matter of law that the group seeking liberation has the most preferred
legal status, and also, usually,
the associated attempt
to reduce all legal statuses to a
single one. So, the elimination of ecclesiastical courts and aristocratic privileges, along with the elimination of serfdom, results in the single category
of citizen [which, at any given historical moment, may or may not include everyone in the
society, of course]. Once again, although the rationale for such a legal change
may be the rejection of some theory of racial
superiority, the change
consists in the alteration in legal status,
not in the success in persuading everyone to reject the theory
that justified the old system of differential statuses.
All of this is obvious and well-known. I emphasize it because I want to suggest that all subsequent
elaborations and developments of the notion
of racism are parasitic on this original notion of legal statuses.
Immediately, of course, it is discovered that the elimination of the legal disabilities does not bring about everything that the liberated
group has been seeking. A former slave in Alabama
may be legally permitted to own land, row crops,
hire laborers, and sell his produce, but he cannot
find a white man to sell him land, etc. "No Irish need apply." "Coloreds to the back of the bus."
There is no question in anyone's mind that differential, discriminatory decisions are being made on the basis of race, even though Negroes
and Whites have in law the same right to own land, enter into contracts, and so forth. Now, what is needed is not the removal
of laws, but laws positively
designed to force people to stop these differential practices. And beyond that, of course,
are needed penalties
to enforce the laws,
and law enforcement officials ready
and able to carry out the enforcement.
Before, an employer
couldn't hire a slave even if she wanted to, for wage labor is a legally enforceable contract, and slaves have no standing
in a court of law to make and
enforce contracts. How she feels about
Nigras is irrelevant. She may have the warmest
of feelings for them. Nor do questions of social pressure
and such arise. She is no more legally allowed to hire a slave than an employer today is permitted
to hire an alien without
a Green Card (though, of course, they do - and so did employers
hire slaves in the Old South, but that is neither here nor there.]
The natural thing to say about the situation at this point is that it is one of virtual slavery [see Proudhon's famous remark that property is theft, or the coining of the marvelously powerful
phrase, "wage slavery," the force of which is now lost on those for whom slavery is not even a memory.] In other words, it seems natural to say that these discriminatory practices, designed to single out just exactly those
who, under the old regime, suffered
from the ascription of a differential legal status, are no different from or in effect the same as the
old system of legal slavery.
To some extent, this way of speaking is simply campaign
rhetoric, but it is also designed to force people
whose attention has been focused
on the legal issues to recognize that extra-legal or post-legal ways have been found to perpetuate the disabilities that were originally legally imposed. But of course
such a way of speaking involves a shift in the original meaning of the term.
Now, we see a series of further shifts.
Even after laws are passed,
and even to some extent enforced, one sees two patterns of events or sets of phenomena to which the name "racism" becomes attached. First of all, and very distressingly [it is important to remember this - one must never forget the high hopes with which those fighting
against the disadvantaged status of some group greet first the elimination of differential legal statuses and then the imposition of laws
requiring equal treatment of persons who are equal before the law] it happens again and again that patterns of differential treatment continue, even in the face of laws against such treatment, because people
in positions to make decisions - bank managers granting
mortgage loans, landlords
renting apartments, employers
hiring workers and then promoting
those who have been hired, college admissions officers, etc. continue
to make differential judgments because
of their private
attitudes toward racial
differences, either independently of or in contravention of the law. At this point, in the absence of the legal justification of differential legal statuses, these individuals justify
such behavior to themselves or others by appeal to evaluative stereotypes or even some more general theory
of innate racial differences.
Even more difficult to deal with, conceptually, are two
further forms of differential treatment,
neither of which involves a conscious act of discriminatory judgment on the part of any individual. First of all, people
in positions of decision-making may make judgments that they themselves
believe to be objective and unaffected by considerations of race, but which others,
looking at them, can see to be based on systematic misperceptions - biases - that shape their evaluations. Calling such behavior
"racist," and calling
those who exhibit it "racists," can be understood
in either of two ways, not always distinguished:
either it is a way of saying that these people
unconsciously, subconsciously, or in a self-deceiving manner, actually hold the sorts of beliefs
that would, in those consciously holding them, issue in differential treatment of people on the basis of race;
or, something
quite different, it is a way of saying that it is as though these
people held such views or attitudes, even though they don't, and hence that they are no better than,
or have the same effect
as, someone enforcing
a legal system of differential statuses. Secondly, practices of discriminatory treatment may become
encoded in, built into, the administrative and bureaucratic procedures
of an institution such as a law court, an army, a college, or a corporation, in such a way that discriminatory
treatment
is reproduced even when none
of the
individuals administering the institution hold, either consciously or unconsciously, discriminatory beliefs. To take a familiar example,
colleges may administer
an admissions procedure
based heavily on SAT scores,
which scores in turn reflect
the degree to which those taking them have had middle class experiences [by way of the sorts
of "A is to B as C is to X" examples they use, etc.], with the consequence that the admissions officers will make choices biased toward middle class applicants regardless of whether they themselves have, consciously or otherwise, a bias toward middle class applicants. This last pattern of institutional behavior comes to be dubbed "institutional racism."
Now, clearly
there are very great differences between legal differentiation of statuses and institutional racism [whatever anyone may think about the relative degree of harm each inflicts]. To refer to them all as racism is,
once again, either
a polemical device, or else- AND THIS IS WHERE THINGS GET IMPORTANT AND INTERESTING- it implies the claim that there is some essence,
which we label racism, the presence of which
manifests itself in different ways, but the nature of which is unchanged, and which is the same essence
in the South
African system
of legally defined racial categories, in the antebellum legal system of slavery, in the virulent
hatred of lynch mobs, in the deliberate lawevading practices of red-lining insurance companies, and in the admissions practices
of a college whose admissions officers
are trying, unsuccessfully, to overcome the built-in bias of their own admissions regulations. Now, this may in fact be true, but it is at least worth pointing out that
the very same people who forcefully reject "essentialism" in general are prone to employ
such terms as "racism" in ways that make sense only if one supposes
that the word names some such essence.
There is one last stage in this progressive development, the roots and implications of which are rather curious
and surprising. The accusation of racism is, of course, an example of the sort of ideological critique
that Mannheim analyses.
The accusation of racism makes no sense
in the South American context.
To accuse someone
in South Africa
of treating people differentially on the basis of race has about the same force as the accusation
in this country that voters are treated
differently according to whether they are registered or not. The obvious answer is, but of course!
It's the law! To accuse someone with a "No
Irish need apply" sign in his front window of discriminating against
the Irish is fatuous. But to accuse someone of racism who claims to be hiring
on the basis of merit is to attack
her integrity, her honesty, and thereby to show her up to be something
other than she claims to be. When accusations of racism are combined with the notion of institutional racism, and the unstated
premise is invoked of a secret
essence present in the same form and virulence in all cases whether
acknowledged or not, then one has indeed a very powerful polemical weapon.
Many people who are extremely eager not to have what they consider
to be the morally or politically wrong views develop
a hypersensitivity to this sort of ideological attack, fearful that they will discover themselves to have been guilty of harboring, unbeknownst to themselves, the hidden virus of the essence, racism. The result is a phenomenon with the most striking affinities
to the behavior of the seventeenth and eighteenth century Puritans. The Puritans, who had embraced
the doctrine of predestination [according
to which God, from all eternity, has preordained who is saved and who is damned],
were faced with the soul-numbing task of trying
to ascertain whether
they were among the elect, the saved. At stake was nothing less
than eternal salvation, and the question was, by hypothesis, already decided. One's
behavior therefore could not earn or lose salvation. All it could do was reveal whether
one had in fact been chosen by God to be among the elect.
The solution of many Puritans was to adopt the
practice of keeping
diaries, in which they wrote, without planning, editing, or forethought, their thoughts and actions. They would then read the diaries, created
by a kind of free association, for evidences of election or damnation.
Inasmuch as an easy confidence in one's salvation
could well be a
sign of sinful pride, and thus
of damnation, while a too great dejection
and self -deprecation could be evidence that the Holy Spirit was not within, you will see that this practice was destined
to leave one in a state of perpetual uncertainty and torment.
Much the same sort of thing can be seen among
those who examine themselves and each
other endlessly for signs of racism, sexism,
etc. Once again,
we see the wisdom of Max Weber's observation that much modern secular
behavior is best understood as a secularization of a distinctively Protestant ethic.
Well, where does this leave us? I suggest, at the very least, that it shows us some of
the complexities in the concept
of racism, which is used these days as though it were the name of a familiar vegetable or a well-known rock star. Think now of the compound
word [if I may call it that] "racism, sexism, and classism" that I called
into question in the last class. At the very least- as Mecke's shrewd intervention shows- it should be
obvious that the historical development of the concept of sexism is different from that of racism, and that both are different from the more recent
development of the notion of classism [whatever that is - I must say I'm really not sure]. To use that formula is, whether one wants to or not, to buy into the claim that these are the names of three essences
that may or may not lurk in people, in institutions, in utterances, or in attitudes, the presence of which makes the people, institutions, practices, or attitudes in some way reprehensible. If you don't endorse this appeal to an essence that can meaningfully be said to reside in, or
to characterize, a person,
an institution, a practice, and an attitude
[!!], then you have the task, before using the terms
again, of thinking
through what you mean by them, and what you intend to presuppose when you invoke them.
This is just the sort of activity Orwell is trying to get us to engage in. It is also the reason for our spending
most of the semester on substantive materials
rather than on abstract theorizing. I am going
to try to stop you each time you idly fall into a lazy use of such language as "racism," when talking about a
novel or an ethnographical study or an account
of the politics or culture of Iraq or Saudi Arabia or the Maghrib.
4 comments:
Towards the latter part of the essay there are a few references to "South America". I suspect that South Africa is what was intended in all those cases.
Quite right. Thank you. It got changed in the conversion from PDF to WORD file and I did not catch it. Done in once more by technology! Rats. I have corrected it in the post.
Dear Professor Wolff,
I would love to see a copy of the syllabus for this course. Would you be willing to post it, or email it?
Thanks,
Adam Valenstein
Adam, I am engaged in a death struggle with my printer, which does not seem to want to scan things, even though it knows perfectly well that it is supposed to be able to. If you email me an address, I will mail you a copy of the syllabus by snail mail.
Post a Comment