My recent posts have provoked a stream of quite interesting
comments, which as yet I have not responded to, so rather than reply in the
comments section, I have decided to write an omnium gatherum post in which I try to address some of the many
questions that have been raised.
Let me begin with two comments [or rather three, actually],
by Andrew Blais and Warren Goldfarb, that take me back quite a way to my early
days as student and young Instructor, in the 1950's and early 1960's. Andrew Blais asks me some pointed questions
about my relation to Quine's nominalism and whether it is in any way related to
my oft-expressed belief that we must struggle to translate metaphors into
arguments if we are to make them clear.
My initial reaction to this question was that I had never been much
interested in the Nominalism-Platonism debate and thought that it had no impact
at all on my thinking about Philosophy.
But then I recalled Martin Jay's wonderful account in The Dialectical Imagination of his
interviews with the surviving members of the Frankfurt School for Social
Research. Jay asked some of the leading
members of the School, who had sought refuge in America from Nazism [many at
the New School for Social Research in Manhattan], what significance there might
be in the fact that almost all of them were upper middle class assimilated
German Jews. These were folks -- Herbert
Marcuse, Hannah Arendt, Theodor Adorno, Erich Fromm, et al. -- who were capable
of discerning deep ideological resonances and complexities in the unlikeliest
artifacts of popular culture, and yet they all brushed the question aside and
said there was no significance to it at all.
Now, I studied with Quine and Goodman when I was not yet
eighteen years old. How plausible is it
that I was blithely unaffected by the philosophical issue that at that time
completely absorbed them? Good grief, my
first serious college term paper, written my Freshman year, was a
"Calculus of Size" using Nelson Goodman's nominalist Logic of
Individuals as it was set forth in his first book, The Structure of Appearance.
Would I believe Aristotle if he said he had been uninfluenced by
studying with Plato? Or Marx, if he said
that although Hegel might have been in the air in Berlin, he had not inhaled?
Quine was meticulous about the niceties of formal logic in a
way that he thought mathematicians were not.
I imbibed the distinction between use and mention with my mother's milk,
as it were. So, if I may view myself
objectively, it seems indisputable that I was influenced by whatever Quine,
Goodman, and certain other members of the Harvard Philosophy Department [most
notably C. I. Lewis] thought were the important philosophical questions. I can recall vividly staying up all night
puzzling over the analytic/synthetic distinction and rushing into the Adams
House dining room on Sunday morning to tell Stanley Cavell what I had
discovered, only to be dismissed by Stanley and his guest, poet John Hollander,
with the languid remark, "Please, not before breakfast."
There can be no doubt that my conception of clarity comes
directly from that handful of analytic philosophers with whom I studied as a
boy, even if the formal issue of nominalism was never on my mind.
Blais goes on to ask, "Why is it that all
the great philosophers (the ones that you have explicated, for example) have
all left posterity complicated argumentative structures that rest on metaphors
that need so much effort to explain?"
I think I know the answer to that one.
The very greatest philosophers are never content with neat, precise
superficial explications of reasonably transparent questions. They are constantly struggling to put into
words insights they have, sometimes only dimly, into very deep and complex
questions, the articulation of which forces them beyond whatever is the
received and widely understood state of the art when they are working. They are unwilling to let go of those
insights, even if they are not yet able to state them clearly. So they grasp at metaphorical articulations
that keep alive as much as possible of the insights. Sometimes they are then able to restate those
insights clearly and precisely, but often it is left to us, coming after them,
to do that work. But if they are so
brilliant, why can they not do this themselves?
I will answer with a metaphor.
When I was young, the four minute mile was the unattainable goal of
every world-class long distance runner. Finally,
in 1954 [as I was preparing to take the famously formidable Prelims in the
Harvard Philosophy Department] Roger Bannister broke the four minute barrier in
a race at Oxford University. Pretty
soon, all the great runners were running sub-four minute miles, and these days
good high school runners can do it. But
until John Bannister did it, it seemed impossible.
Which, by a process of Shandean association, brings me to
Warren Goldfarb's interesting response to my facetious post about first and
last lines. Professor Goldfarb writes
that "in the late 1950s J.L. Austin and my late colleague Roderick Firth
were planning a book of opposing views in epistemology that they hoped to title
Price and Prejudice (after H.H. Price, the stalwart of English
sense-data theory)." The late 1950's is just when I was writing my
doctoral dissertation under Firth's direction and teaching in the Department as
an Instructor when Firth was acting as Chair.
I never heard about the plan for a book with Austin, but I can easily
imagine it. Roderick Firth was a wonderful
man -- ramrod straight, slender, a man of impeccable moral character, with a
charming little smile flirting with the edges of his mouth. I heard that as a Quaker he "witnessed"
during the Viet Nam War by attending public demonstrations. It was Firth who gave me an invaluable little
piece of advice on writing my dissertation.
He put a pair of x and y axes on the board and then drew two lines -- a
straight line rising slowly from the origin, and an arc curving up from the
origin farther and farther above the straight line. "The straight line is your ability to
write a good dissertation, rising slowly as time passes," he said. "The curved line represents the sort of
dissertation you think you should write, and as time passes and you do not
finish, it rises faster and faster. The
sooner you finish, the smaller the gap will be between the dissertation you do
write and the dissertation you think you should write." It was the best advice I ever received, and I
responded by writing the entire dissertation, from the time I chose the topic
until the day I handed it in, in eighteen months.
My first year as a graduate student, I took a
reading course with Firth. I read
Hastings Rashdall's Theory of Good and
Evil and Henry Sidgwick's Methods of
Ethics and Collingwood and Moore and Ross and Ewing and lord knows what
else. I am sure I am a better person for
it all, but I found it hopelessly boring.
I actually went off to Europe for my wanderjahr
thinking I would write a dissertation on ethics, but by the time I got home, I
had given that up and turned instead to Kant and Hume. Whew!
Close call.
Professor Goldfarb mentions H. H. Price. How that brings back memories! Price's book, Hume's Theory of the External World, now long forgotten I am sure,
had an enormous impact on me during the time when I was so deeply engaged with
the Treatise. Those were the days when Oxford and Cambridge
were the Promised Land to American philosophers. It is all associated in my mind with those
severe black volumes that Oxford University Press put out, many of which still
grace my shelves here in Chapel Hill.
Which
brings me to Andrew Levine, my old student, now retired [I
believe.] I have not yet gotten around
to reading Andy's book on Marx, which I shall, so I must hold serious comment
for the moment, but I could not let his name pass without noting that for a
brief moment [his "fifteen minutes of fame," pace Andy Warhol], he was known on television as Professor
Backwards because of his bizarre ability [demonstrated, if I remember
correctly, on the Johnny Carson Show] to repeat what someone says backwards --
not word by word, but phoneme by phoneme, so that it sounds like what a person
who does not speak Chinese thinks Chinese sounds like.
Well, I think that is enough, though it only
scratches the surface of the interesting comments that have popped up
lately. Thank you all and keep them
coming.
4 comments:
Could you also say something about C I Lewis? The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy states
"Clarence Irving (C.I.) Lewis was perhaps the most important American academic philosopher active in the 1930s and 1940s. He made major contributions in epistemology and logic, and, to a lesser degree, ethics. Lewis was also a key figure in the rie of analytic philosophy in the United States, both through the development and influence of his own writings and through his influence, direct and indirect, on graduate students at Harvard, including some of the leading analytic philosophers of the last half of the 20th century"
I remember glancing at but never actually reading Mind and World Order, and An Analysis of Knowledge of Valuation, when I studied some philosophy in the 1970s. Are those books worth reading now?
WallyVerr, I can say a good deal about Lewis, and will tomorrow. he is, in my opinion, one of the most important philosophers America has produced.
You're misusing the Latin preposition pace. It means "contrary to the opinion of." http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/pace
Oh dear. That's not good. I shall leave it there as an evidence of my limitations. Thank you.
Post a Comment