Part One
The Classical Political Economy
Against Which Marx Writes
Marx called his great work simply Das Kapital,
which is to say Capital (leading his mother, who was rather
disappointed in her son, to remark "if only Karl
had made Capital, instead of just writing about
it.") The subtitle of Marx’s work is “Critique of Political
Economy.” It is thus, in the first instance, a critique not of capitalist
society but rather of what had been written about economics before Marx.
The three great theorists preceding Marx who established the discipline
that was known as Political Economy were the 18th-century French
theorist François Quesney, the 18th-century Scottish theorist Adam
Smith, and the 19th century English theorist David Ricardo.
The late medieval reestablishment of Mediterranean trade and
the influx of precious metals from the new world together produced a
centuries-long inflation in European prices, which in turn led to the
widespread belief that wealth consisted primarily in stores of gold and silver.
Quesnay, examining the success of the 18th-century French economy,
advanced the radically new theory that national wealth consisted not in stores
of gold but in the products of a nation’s agriculture. In defending this view,
Quesnay made central to his analysis a concept on which all economic theory
came to depend: the concept of reproduction.
Reproduction is a very simple idea, but it is so important
that we must spend a little time talking about it to make it absolutely clear.
Agriculture in the Northern hemisphere produces a single crop each
year. As soon as the snows melt and the ground softens, seeds are
planted. They are tended during the spring and summer until, in the fall, the
crops are harvested. A portion of the crop is set aside to serve as seed in the
next season. Thus, the output of one season serves as an input into
the next season and this cyclical process of reproduction continues, year after
year. The same fundamental cycle of reproduction is exhibited in the production
of the tools with which the peasants work. The shovels and axes used in one
season of agriculture are made from the wood and metal produced in the previous
season.
A cyclical structure of the process of reproduction is of course
exhibited also in the population as well. This generation’s parents are the
last generation’s children who are themselves the product of the previous
generation’s parents.
This elementary idea is, as we shall see, the foundation on
which are built the elaborate mathematical models of the 20th century
re-examination of the classical traditional political economy.
In An Inquiry into the
Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, Adam Smith poses three
questions, the answers to which serve to constitute or found the discipline of political
economy. What, he asks, is the real nature of economic wealth – of the wealth
of nations? In what way, and by what institutional processes, is wealth distributed
among the several classes of society? And what are the causes of an increase in
national wealth, which is to say, of economic growth? His first answer, in
effect, establishes the physical quantities approach as fundamental. His second
answer specifies both who gets the
physical surplus and how they get it.
And his third answer tells us what is
done with the surplus.
To the first question Smith replies, in contradistinction to
the mercantilists, that the real wealth of a nation consists in the “necessaries
and conveniencies of life which it annually consumes,” not in the gold and
silver hoarded within its boundaries.
His answer to the third question, in brief, is that the progressive
division of labour and the reinvestment of the annual surplus in an expansion
of the scale of production will, together, bring about an increase in real, as
opposed to merely nominal or monetary, wealth.
It is in his attempt to answer the second question that
Smith makes his boldest and most important theoretical advance. The
institutional arrangement through which the wealth of a nation is distributed
to its several classes is the market,
according to Smith, and with his introduction of the concept of natural price he lays the theoretical
foundation for all of the political economy and economic theory that has
followed.
Smith takes up and adapts to his purpose the ancient and very
powerful thesis of the rationality of being – an idea which had for two
millennia served as the basis for philosophical and theological accounts of the
ontological structure of nature and of the relationship of human beings to God
and to being in general.
The central idea is familiar enough and by Smith’s day had
become a commonplace. The universe has been created or organised by a divine being
according to a rational plan, which is embodied in nature in the form of
certain universal laws or structures. The human mind has been created by this same
divine artificer, and has had implanted within it a spark of the divine reason.
To know being is to grasp the rational structure that the creator has imposed
upon it. Our minds are adequate to the task of apprehending the objective
rational order of being precisely because our reason is an imitation of the
creative reason which has constituted the objective order. So nature is
rational and the mind’s power of reason is adequate to the task of apprehending
nature’s rational structure, its laws.
Smith now advances a powerful thesis, extending this
traditional concept of nature. Society, Smith in effect asserts, is a second nature. Despite its conventional
origins, it too has an order governed by laws, and hence it can also become the
object of rational investigation. Indeed, left to itself, society will function
regularly and in a law-governed manner. As he argues in his earlier Theory of Moral Sentiments, in a passage
devoted to a criticism of Hobbes and others, “human society, when we
contemplate it in a certain abstract and philosophical light, appears like a
great, an immense machine, whose regular and harmonious movements produce a
thousand agreeable effects.”
Inasmuch as human society is not the intentional product of
a purposeful and rational creator, it is not immediately clear on what grounds
we can attribute to it a rational structure whose formal characteristics can
become the object of our scientific investigations. In order to get over this difficulty,
Smith joins to the ancient doctrine of the rationality of being a more modern
notion: the public benefits of private self-interest. In effect, he seeks to deduce the order of society from the
interactions of countless persons whose actions can be comprehended,
anticipated, and calculated precisely because they are grounded in rationally
comprehensible self-interest. In place of the mind’s capacity to grasp God’s
plan, Smith invokes the mind’s capacity to grasp the rationally self-interested
plans of other human beings. The rational order of society is thus the unintended
consequence of the actions of privately rational agents.
Since there is no overarching goal, no telos toward which individual actions are oriented, it is essential
both to the objective rationality of society and to the subjective rationality
of our cognition of society that each individual agent act in a
self-interested, and hence calculable, fashion. Acts of beneficence or charity,
or acts done from habit or custom, because they spring from the non-rational
portions of the soul, will be inherently unpredictable and incalculable. Smith
recognises this fact in one of the best known of the many quotable passages in The Wealth of Nations: “It is not from the
benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker, that we expect our
dinner, but from their regard to their own interest. We address ourselves, not
to their humanity but to their self-love, and never talk to them of our own
necessities but of their advantages.”
We arrive thus at the concept of the market as a system of individual interactions which
naturally and unintendedly combine in stable patterns, regulated by rational
laws. According to Smith, the key to an understanding of the market, and
thereby of society, is the concept of economic exchange, which he traces, with
characteristic eighteenth-century wit and superficiality, to a “certain
propensity in human nature... to truck, barter, and exchange one thing for
another.” Announcing his intention to investigate “the rules which men
naturally observe in exchanging [goods] either for money or for one another,”
he introduces the distinction between value in use and value in exchange which
was to be taken up by Ricardo, by Marx, and indeed by virtually all economists
up to the present day. The passage is worth quoting in full:
The word VALUE, it is
to be observed, has two different meanings, and sometimes expresses the utility
of some particular object, and sometimes the power of purchasing other goods
which the possession of that object conveys. The one may be called “value in use,”
the other “value in exchange.” The things which have the greatest value in use
have frequently little or no value in exchange; and on the contrary, those
which have the greatest value in exchange have frequently little or no value in
use. Nothing is more useful than water: but it will purchase scarce anything;
scarce anything can be had in exchange for it. A diamond, on the contrary, has scarce
any value in use; but a very great quantity of other goods may frequently be
had in exchange for it.
In order to investigate
the principles which regulate the exchangeable value of commodities, I shall
endeavour to shew.
First, what is the real
measure of this exchangeable value; or wherein consists the real price of commodities.
Secondly, what are the
different parts of which this real price is composed or made up.
And, lastly, what are
the different circumstances which sometimes raise some or all of these
different parts of price above, and sometimes sink them below their natural or
ordinary rate; or, what are the causes which sometimes hinder the market price,
that is, the actual price of commodities, from coinciding exactly with what may
be called their natural price.
Smith now undertakes, by a series of logical and conceptual manoeuvres,
to define a new object of investigation, namely natural price. He also advances a theory of natural price – more
precisely, a theory of the factors which regulate or determine natural price. But
as we shall see, his attempts at a theory are almost entirely unsuccessful.
it might
be useful to ask at the outset why such a theory is so important to a critical
understanding of capitalist economy and society. Briefly, the answer is this:
the central social and economic issue in any society is how the annual surplus
shall be divided up, and what shall be done with it once it has been divided. The
question of distribution is important in its own right, and important as well
through its implications for questions of economic growth, political
domination, and cultural hegemony.
In a capitalist society, the social product is distributed to the several classes in the form of wages, rents, profits, and interest. Some of what is distributed is required for the reproduction of the economy and society at the existing level of output and activity. The rest is surplus, and may be wasted, consumed unproductively, or invested to expand the scope and level of production. As we shall soon have occasion to note, what are actually distributed are quanta of value in the form of money, not (by and large) physical stocks of corn, iron, or theology books. In order to determine how much money is allotted to workers as wages, to landlords as rents, to entrepreneurs as profits, to financiers as interest, and so forth, and in order as well to determine what that money will buy, we must have a theory of the factors influencing and determining prices, wages, rents, profits, and interest. Such a theory is precisely a theory of price, or, in the language current when Smith wrote, a theory of value.
In the unfolding of the argument in The Wealth of Nations, Smith advances his theory first, and only
then presents an explicit definition of natural, as opposed to market, price.
But we shall reverse the order of our analysis, for the concept of natural
price is actually Smith’s major theoretical contribution to the discipline of
political economy.
There is in every
society or neighbourhood an ordinary or average rate both of wages and profit
in every different employment of labour and stock. This rate is naturally regulated,
as I shall show hereafter, partly by the general circumstances of the society,
their riches or poverty, their advancing, stationary, or declining condition;
and partly by the particular nature of each employment.
There is likewise in every
society or neighbourhood an ordinary or average rate of rent, which is
regulated too, as I shall show hereafter, partly by the general circumstances
of the society or neighbourhood in which the land is situated, and partly by
the natural or improved fertility of the land.
These ordinary or
average rates may be called the natural rates of wages, profit, and rent, at
the time and place in which they commonly prevail.
When the price of any commodity
is neither more nor less than what is sufficient to pay the rent of the land,
the wages of the labour, and the profits of the stock employed in raising,
preparing, and bringing it to market, according to their natural rates, the commodity
is then sold for what may be called its natural price.
As introduced here, the concept of natural price does not rise
much above the level of the most naive observation of surface phenomena.
Practical men of affairs become aware, as they conduct their business, that a
certain wage, rent, or rate of return is customary in a particular locale.
Without asking why, they come to
expect that they shall have to pay those rates, and like the occupants of
Plato’s cave, they may even become adept at predicting fluctuations in the shadows
on the wall. In the most elementary attempt at theory, Smith identifies the natural
price of a commodity with the sum of the amounts which the entrepreneur must lay
out in order to produce the good plus the profit which he himself is to reap.
Now, however, Smith rapidly advances his analysis with a series
of arguments which carry him well beyond mere observation to genuine theory.
First of all, he justifies his inclusion of the natural profit as a component
of the natural price of the commodity by an appeal to the workings of material
self-interest in a free, competitive market:
The commodity is then
sold [i.e., when its price exactly covers the natural wage, natural rent, and natural
profit] precisely for what it is worth, or for what it really costs the person
who brings it to market; for though in common language what is called the prime
cost of any commodity does not comprehend the profit of the person who is to
sell it again, yet if he sells it at a price which does not allow him the ordinary
rate of profit in his neighbourhood, he is evidently a loser by the trade; since by employing his stock in some other
way he might have made that profit.
As Smith makes clear in the next paragraph, the argument
turns essentially on a number of assumptions concerning the workings of a competitive
market. Each entrepreneur is presumed to be engaged in a rationally self-interested
pursuit of profit, in an economy which permits him to “change his trade as
often as he pleases.” With good, if not perfect, information, entrepreneurs will
quickly learn of opportunities for greater profit in other lines of production,
and unhindered by law or custom, will move their capital freely to follow the
fluctuations of the rate of return.
“The actual price at which any commodity is commonly sold,”
Smith now says, “is called its market price.” Market price is regulated by
the relative strength of supply and demand. As these fluctuate widely, so will
market price. Entrepreneurs, eager for greater profit, respond to the cues of
market price by moving their capital hither and yon, fleeing from sectors of
production in which an excess supply has driven market price below natural price,
and moving toward sectors where an excess of “effectual demand” has driven up market
price and produced a temporary super-profit for the shrewd or fortunate
capitalists engaged in that line of production.
Smith now advances his analysis by the introduction of a
powerful metaphor: “The natural price, therefore,” he says, “is, as it were,
the central price, to which the prices of all commodities are continually
gravitating.”
Although Smith makes very little of the image of natural prices as centres of gravity, it is worth exploring for a bit, because a number of deep and powerful theoretical assumptions are encapsulated within it. The use of the term natural is clearly intended to suggest an objective law-governed system, a “nature” analogous to physical nature, with a rational structure apprehendable by human reason. To characterise natural prices as centres of gravity is to impute to them some causal efficacy, or at least to claim that they could correctly be understood as having causal efficacy in a theoretical model designed to articulate the underlying structure of the market. They are clearly not to be thought of merely as statistical averages or unexplained regularities, but are to be construed rather as centres of force ineluctably drawing market prices to them. As bodies of a system in equilibrium, when displaced from their positions, tend to move back to their equilibrium locations, so prices, displaced momentarily by fluctuations in supply or demand from their natural levels, will tend to move back to their equilibrium positions. What is more, natural prices, like physical centres of gravity, form a system of interacting forces. As the movement of one mass anywhere in Newtonian space affects all other masses, so a change in one natural price will produce alterations in all other natural prices, which changes will then return to affect the original natural price. Smith himself does not draw out the implications of his metaphor, but they are implicit in it, and eventually become explicit in the theory of David Ricardo.
By characterising natural prices as centres of gravity, Smith
encourages us to conceive of them as objectively real determinants of the economic
system. Once we have accepted the distinction between natural price and market
price, we must inevitably ask: What are the determinants of natural price? In
short, Smith sets for himself and for all subsequent political economists the
task of formulating a satisfactory theory
of natural price.
Smith does not yet have a coherent notion of an economy in equilibrium, but the elements of such a notion
are present in his distinction between natural and market price and in his account
of the mechanism by which deviations of market from natural price, brought
about by fluctuations in effective demand, are corrected through the self-interested
responses of rational consumers and entrepreneurs.
Smith grounds his attempt at a theory of natural price in
some elementary assumptions about the subjective tastes and preferences of
individuals. First of all, he takes it for granted that labouring is unpleasant
and painful – something one would engage in only from force of necessity. “Equal
quantities of labour, at all times and places,” Smith asserts without argument,
“[are] of equal value to the labourer. In his ordinary state of health, strength,
and spirits; in the ordinary degree of his skill and dexterity, he must always
lay down the same portion of his ease, his liberty, and his happiness.”
There are powerful theoretical motives for this attempt by Smith to locate something in the economic world whose worth is everywhere and always the same, motives that prompted Ricardo, half a century later, to search for an “invariable standard of value.” The problem is this: the price of a commodity expresses how much of that commodity one will give in the market for other commodities, or, what is the same thing, how much of other commodities one can obtain with the given commodity. The price of a commodity is actually a relation between it and other commodities. A relation, or ratio, changes when either of its terms changes (or, save in special cases, when both terms change). If a bushel of corn will buy more cloth today than it bought yesterday, that may be because something has happened to make corn worth more, or it may equally be because something has happened to make cloth worth less. From the mere fact of the change in their relative value, nothing can be concluded concerning the causes of the change.
Smith was persuaded, as was Ricardo, that a satisfactory theory
of natural price should be able to tell us which of two commodities has changed
in value when the rate of exchange between them alters. To Smith, this could only
mean finding some one special commodity whose value, being constant, would
serve as a standard against which all other commodities could be measured, and
in terms of which we could chart the fluctuations in the value of those other
commodities.
To an earlier age, the precious metals, gold and silver,
might have seemed natural candidates for the role of invariant standard, but
Smith was quite conscious of the fact that the influx of precious metals from
the New World in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries had depressed their
price dramatically. So he hit upon labour as a commodity whose value to its
owners was ever constant: “Labour alone, therefore, never varying in its own
value, is alone the ultimate and real standard by which the value of all commodities
can at all times and places be estimated and compared. It is their real price;
money is their nominal price only.”
If labour never varies in its value, what then determines the
value of other commodities? Smith actually advances three different answers to this question, two of which at least he
somewhat confusedly considers equivalent to one another. His first answer, on which
Ricardo erected his own theory, is that goods
exchange in the market in proportion to the quantities of labour required to
produce them. Although Smith considered this explanation to be correct only
in a primitive state of society, and therefore devoted scarcely a page to it,
it is in fact the theoretically most promising of his three attempts, and will
repay close analysis. Here is the explanation in its entirety, in one of the
best-known passages in the text:
In that early and rude
state of society which precedes both the accumulation of stock and the
appropriation of land, the proportion between the quantities of labour necessary
for acquiring different objects seems to be the only circumstance which can
afford any rule for exchanging them for one another. If among a nation of
hunters, for example, it usually costs twice the labour to kill a beaver which
it does to kill a deer, one beaver should naturally exchange for or be worth two
deer. It is natural that what is usually the produce of two days or two hours
labour, should be worth double of what is usually the produce of one day’s or
one hour’s labour.
What we have here, in the graceful and ingenuous style characteristic of Smith’s exposition, is a theorem in the theory of rational choice. The logic of the proof is clear enough, but a world of presuppositions, abstractions, and simplifications are hidden within it. We are to imagine a state of affairs in which hunters are capable, on average, of catching a beaver in twice the time required to catch a deer. Smith does not say so, but the argument demands that they hunt with their bare hands, for the use of weapons comes under the heading of “the accumulation of stock” and introduces theoretical difficulties which were to remain unsolved until the publication of Ricardo’s Principles. Under the circumstances, let us posit two days' bare-hand hunting per beaver, and one days per deer. It is essential to the argument that all hunters be equally skilled at hunting either beaver or deer, and that there be no economies of scale or efficiencies from specialisation and the division of labour.
Now we are to imagine two hunters, Diana and Orion,
encountering one another in a clearing in the forest after two weeks’ hunting, Diana
bearing ten deer and Orion five beaver (assuming a five-day work week). Let us
suppose that each has declining marginal utility for beaver and deer, and hence
wishes to trade a portion of his or her catch for a portion of the other’s
catch. In what proportions will they be willing to trade, assuming that each is
self-interestedly rational?
To begin with, each views the labour of hunting as painful
and tedious, a cost rather than a benefit, even in the idyllic conditions here
posited. Hence neither will work a day longer than necessary. Furthermore, each
is quite capable of catching a beaver in two days of averagely stressful labour
or a deer in one day of equally stressful labour.
With these premises, we can now deduce what the shape will
be of each hunter’s bargaining space. Suppose that Diana offers to trade one of
her deer for one of Orion’s beaver. After some reflection, Orion will refuse, for
he will reason thus: If I make this trade, I will be in possession of four
beaver and one deer, for which I will have expended ten days’ labour. (Smith
assumes that there are no transaction costs, and that the bargaining process,
being neither a joy nor a labour, does not figure in the calculation.) But if what
I want is four beaver and one deer, I can have them for only nine days’ labour
– eight hunting beaver, and a ninth hunting deer. I can then spend the tenth
day resting, and as I prefer four beaver, one deer, and a day’s rest to four
beaver, one deer, and no rest, clearly this trade is not in my interest. To be sure,
I have already expended ten days’ effort, and that is therefore a sunk cost.
But in future – which is to say, in long-run equilibrium – I would do better to
do all my hunting myself rather than concentrate on beaver and trade for deer.
So Orion rejects Diana’s offer and proposes instead that she
give him three deer for one beaver. By an analogous process of reasoning, Diana
concludes that such a trade will not be in her self- interest, and she rejects
the proposal.
After some time, “by the higgling and bargaining of the market, according to that sort of rough equality which, though not exact, is sufficient for carrying on the business of common life,” Diana comes to see that two deer are the most it is rational for her to part with for one beaver, and Orion in turn comes to see that two deer are the least he will accept for one of his beaver. Since their bargaining spaces intersect at a single point, the two consummate a deal at precisely that point, and so it comes to pass that the going exchange rate for deer and beaver is two deer for one beaver.
I have gone on at such length about so simple an example not
merely because it is the archetype of all such examples in economic theory, but
also because contained within this classic pastoral tale, either explicitly or
implicitly, are many of the theoretical assumptions that play so large a role in
the more sophisticated theories of Ricardo and Marx. We can name, among the principal
assumptions: the total instrumental rationality of the agents, the disutility
of labour, the social achievement of a degree of standardisation and homogenisation
of labouring activity sufficient to allow us to say precisely how long it takes
to catch “a” beaver or “a” deer (as opposed to this beaver or that deer). Also
present, but quite unnoticed by Smith, is the crucially important assumption of
the standardisation of the product –
the beaver and the deer – so that either, by a process of selective breeding, all
beaver have come to be of equal size and usefulness and all deer the same, or
else some way has been found to index the multidimensional variations among beaver
and deer so that one can calculate the standard time required to catch the standard
beaver or deer.
Equally important is the willingness of Diana and Orion to adopt purely functional attitudes toward their hunting activity. Neither imbues the hunt with a religious, mythic, aesthetic, or familial significance that would interfere with the cost/benefit calculations out of which arises the natural price of two beaver for one deer.
In addition to the theory that commodities exchange in
proportion to the amount of labour required to produce them – a theory which came to be known as the “labour
embodied” standard – Smith also argues that commodities exchange in proportion to
the amount of labour which they can, in effect, command – what came to be known as the “labour commanded” theory of
price. Smith argues thus:
Every man is rich or
poor according to the degree in which he can afford to enjoy the necessaries,
conveniencies, and amusements of human life. But after the division of labour
has once thoroughly taken place, it is but a very small part of these with which
a man’s own labour can supply him. The far greater part of them he must derive
from the labour of other people, and he must be rich or poor according to the
quantity of that labour which he can command, or which he can afford to
purchase. The value of any commodity, therefore, to the person who possesses
it, and who means not to use or consume it himself, but to exchange it for
other commodities, is equal to the quantity of labour which it enables him to
purchase or command. Labour, therefore, is the real measure of the exchangeable
value of all commodities.27
It is not immediately clear how we are to interpret these and other similar remarks by Smith. Perhaps the most natural interpretation is simply to construe Smith as claiming that commodities will exchange in proportion to the quantities of labour which each will buy. If a bushel of corn will exchange in the market for half a day’s labour (which is to say that I can hire a worker for half a day for a wage of one bushel of corn), and if a yard of cloth will exchange in the market for a full day’s labour, then two bushels of corn, Smith might be saying, will exchange for one yard of cloth. For:
1 bu. corn = 1/2 day’s labour
and
1 yd. cloth = 1 day’s labour
imply that
(1 bu. corn)/(l yd. cloth) = (1/2 day’s labour)/(l day’s
labour)
= 1/2
or
2 bu, corn = 1 yd. cloth.
But this claim, although true, is trivial. It amounts to
nothing more than the assertion that a consistent, complete price system
exists. So although many of Smith’s assertions appear to reduce to the claim that
commodities will exchange in proportion to the quantity of labour they can
purchase in the market, we must search for a more interesting interpretation of
the text if we are to rescue Smith from triviality.
According to a second interpretation, for which a good deal of
textual evidence can be cited, a commodity can be said to command a quantity of
labour in the sense of commanding or purchasing or exchanging for another
commodity into whose production a certain quantity of labour has gone. Thus, if
it takes ten hours of labour, one way or another, to produce one yard of cloth,
and if two bushels of corn will purchase a yard of cloth, then one bushel of corn
might be said to “command” five hours of labour. As Smith says: “The power
which that possession [of a fortune] immediately and directly conveys to him
[who possesses it], is the power of purchasing; a certain command over all the
labour, or over all the produce of labour which is then in the market. His
fortune is greater or less, precisely in proportion to the extent of this
power, or to the quantity either of other men’s labour, or, what is the same thing, of the produce
of other men’s labour, which it enables him to purchase or command.”
Smith does not distinguish this labour-commanded theory of price from the labour-embodied theory that holds in the “early and rude state” and on occasion he seems to identify the two. Ricardo was exceedingly critical of Smith for this confusion (as Ricardo saw it), and indeed it is not difficult to see that in general the two theories are quite distinct. Suppose that under current conditions of agricultural production, it takes one hour of labour to produce one bushel of corn. Then a bushel of corn embodies one hour of labour. Suppose as well that an agricultural labourer’s wage for an eight-hour day is four bushels of corn. Then one bushel of corn commands two hours of labour. A rise or fall in the wage, unaccompanied by an alteration in the technology of corn production, or alternatively a change in the technique of corn production unaccompanied by a change in the wage, will cause one of these two quantities (labour commanded or labour embodied) to vary while the other remains unchanged, thus decisively proving that they are distinct.
As soon as we leave the early and rude state and enter a
society in which the appropriation of land and the accumulation of stock have
taken place, the simple beaver/deer explanation of exchange ratios ceases to
apply. To see why this is so, let us imagine that while Diana and Orion have
been out hunting, Demeter has been raising grain on her ten-acre plot of land.
Before she begins her planting, she must spend 100 days felling trees, pulling stumps
(also, for the sake of theoretical simplicity, with her bare hands), and
generally preparing the field. Another 100 days of planting, weeding, and reaping
produces, at the end of the year, a total harvest of 800 bushels of corn. The
question now arises in what proportions will Demeter, Diana, and Orion exchange
their corn, deer, and beaver with one another? The terms of trade between Diana
and Orion have not altered – two deer for one beaver. But when they attempt to
enter into stable patterns of exchange with Demeter, many troublesome problems
crop up. Demeter has spent 200 days raising 800 bushels of grain, which is to say
she has spent a day’s labour for each four bushels she has grown. She therefore
proposes to exchange four bushels of grain for one deer, or eight bushels for
one beaver. At first sight, this might appear a reasonable proposal, but
neither Diana nor Orion is likely to accept it, for in fact it is heavily
biased in Demeter s favour.
The point, of course, is that once her field has been cleared
by the 100 days’ labour, it is fit for cultivation for many seasons, not for
one season only. We can imagine Orion reasoning to himself thus: I now hunt 200
days each year for an annual catch of 100 beaver. If I want 80 bushels of
grain, I can obtain it by spending 10 days clearing an acre of forest and 10
more days cultivating the soil. The 20 days lost to beaver hunting will
diminish my annual catch by 10 beaver, so it might seem equally reasonable for
me to hunt the year round and exchange with Demeter 10 of my beaver for 80
bushels of her grain, at a ratio of 1 beaver to 8 bushels. But the following
year, I shall still want 80 bushels of grain and 90 beaver (or else I shall be
able, if that is what I have, to trade without trouble). In that time period,
since my acre will already be cleared, I will have to work only 190 days total
– 180 to catch 90 beaver and 10 on the cleared land to raise 80 bushels of
grain. It follows that I can do better by hunting and farming than by hunting
and trading with Demeter. So I will reject her offer.
The same reasoning leads Diana to refuse Demeter’s proposed
terms of trade.
If we could specify how long the field will remain cleared –
over how many cycles of production – we might be able to come up with a
proposal that would win the agreement of Diana, Orion, and Demeter. But now we realise
that there are other factors to be taken account of, even in this simplest and most
fanciful of examples. Diana’s bow takes some time to fashion (assuming that she
has moved beyond bare-hand hunting), and it lasts for more than one season. So
too does Demeter’s hoe. And the wood from which the bow and the hoe are made is
of a special sort, carefully gathered at an earlier time and aged before being
worked. In addition, Diana and Orion cannot so easily shift to agriculture, for
the best land has already been spoken for by farmers who will demand a price
for its use.
In short, we have come face to face with that “appropriation
of land and accumulation of stock” which Smith correctly identified as the
reason why goods fail to exchange in proportion to the labour time directly
required for their production. Smith himself offers a rather curious and
superficial explanation for this failure:
As soon as stock has accumulated
in the hands of particular persons, some of them will naturally employ it in
setting to work industrious people... in order to make a profit by the sale of their
work [the employer] could have no interest to employ [the workmen], unless he
expected from the sale of their work something more than what was sufficient to
replace his stock to him; and he could have no interest to employ a great stock
rather than a small one, unless his profits were to bear some proportion to the
extent of his stock.
And, a bit later on in the same chapter:
As soon as the land of
any country has all become private property, the landlords, like all other men,
love to reap where they never sowed, and demand a rent even for its natural
produce.
But these “explanations,” although charming, are not really
explanations at all. Smith tells us that the prudent entrepreneur is unwilling to venture his capital without
a return, and that the greedy, feckless landlord seeks to use his monopoly of
the land to get something for nothing. But Smith has not explained what
determines how great a return the entrepreneur can reasonably expect, and he has
therefore not told us what effect the profits of stock will have on the rate at
which commodities exchange with one another. (Strictly speaking, he has also
not explained why the entrepreneur can rationally expect any return at all on
his investment, but that is an objection first raised by Marx, and we shall
have to postpone consideration of it for a bit.)
At this point, Smith offers what some readers of The Wealth of Nations have taken to be a theory of price, namely the so-called adding-up theory. As Smith says, “when the price of any commodity is neither more nor less than what is sufficient to pay the rent of the land, the wages of the labour, and the profits of the stock employed in raising, preparing, and bringing it to market, according to their natural rates, the commodity is then sold for what may be called its natural price.” But this is not a theory of natural price. It is, as we have seen, merely a definition of the term “natural price”.
In fact, Smith has no theory of the determination of natural
price. Hence, he has no theory of wages, rents, and profits, and so no theory
as well of the distribution of the social product among the several great
classes of society. Nevertheless, Smith has successfully identified the object
of investigation of political economy, namely the market, and he has formulated
the central analytical concept, natural price. It remained for David Ricardo,
forty-one years later, to advance the first coherent, fully worked-out theory
of natural price.
7 comments:
First, an excellent and insightful article that was a pleasure to read.
Just a minor quibble. In the quote on Adam Smith, the ellipsis I believe leaves out the most important part, which explains why there is a profit for capital. First, Prof. Wolff's quote:
As soon as stock has accumulated in the hands of particular persons, some of them will naturally employ it in setting to work industrious people... in order to make a profit by the sale of their work [the employer] could have no interest to employ [the workmen], unless he expected from the sale of their work something more than what was sufficient to replace his stock to him; and he could have no interest to employ a great stock rather than a small one, unless his profits were to bear some proportion to the extent of his stock.
The expanded quote (emphasis mine):
As soon as stock has accumulated in the hands of particular persons, some of them will naturally employ it in setting to work industrious people, whom they will supply with materials and subsistence, in order to make a profit by the sale of their work, or by what their labour adds to the value of the materials. In exchanging the complete manufacture either for money, for labour, or for other goods, over and above what may be sufficient to pay the price of the materials, and the wages of the workmen, something must be given for the profits of the undertaker of the work who hazards his stock in this adventure. The value which the workmen add to the materials, therefore, resolves itself in this ease into two parts, of which the one pays their wages, the other the profits of their employer upon the whole stock of materials and wages which he advanced. He could have no interest to employ them, unless he expected from the sale of their work something more than what was sufficient to replace his stock to him; and he could have no interest to employ a great stock rather than a small one, unless his profits were to bear some proportion to the extent of his stock.
The part directly after makes clear that profit is only for hazarding capital stock and nothing else (emphasis mine):
The profits of stock, it may perhaps be thought are only a different name for the wages of a particular sort of labour, the labour of inspection and direction. They are, however, altogether different, are regulated by quite different principles, and bear no proportion to the quantity, the hardship, or the ingenuity of this supposed labour of inspection and direction. They are regulated altogether by the value of the stock employed, and are greater or smaller in proportion to the extent of this stock.
As an aside, the purpose of capital markets is to allocate capital to its highest and best use. When investors do that effectively, they earn a rate of return that is higher than the normal rate of the market, i.e., alpha returns being the excess over beta returns.
"...the purpose of capital markets is to allocate capital to its highest and best use."
1873, 1893, 1907, 1929, 2008... It would be nice if the world worked that way.
2008...selected quotes
The Government Did It
It is popular to take low lending standards as proof that the free market has failed, that the system that is supposed to reward productive behavior and punish unproductive behavior has failed to do so. Yet this claim ignores that for years irrational lending standards have been forced on lenders by the federal Community Reinvestment Act (CRA) and rewarded (at taxpayers' expense) by multiple government bodies.
The CRA forces banks to make loans in poor communities, loans that banks may otherwise reject as financially unsound. Under the CRA, banks must convince a set of bureaucracies that they are not engaging in discrimination, a charge that the act encourages any CRA-recognized community group to bring forward. Otherwise, any merger or expansion the banks attempt will likely be denied. But what counts as discrimination?
The government has promoted bad loans not just through the stick of the CRA but through the carrot of Fannie Mae and Freddie Mac, which purchase, securitize and guarantee loans made by lenders and whose debt is itself implicitly guaranteed by the federal government. This setup created an easy, artificial profit opportunity for lenders to wrap up bundles of subprime loans and sell them to a government-backed buyer whose primary mandate was to "promote homeownership," not to apply sound lending standards.
Sometimes it's not what government did but didn't do, like in 1929 when the government, as the spender of last resort, failed to spend to keep the economy from falling into depression.
1. Source of that just-so story?
2. Blaming "government" like blaming "congress" is an evasion. Lots of effort and money went into recreating Mellon-world. Greenspan did admit to being too optimistic.
3. Lest we forget: https://robertreich.substack.com/p/today-50-years-ago-henry-kissinger?utm_campaign=email-post&r=2m9qt&utm_source=substack&utm_medium=email
It's all too much to spend much time on, but unless I'm mistaken the prolific commenter doesn't really engage with the material the professor presents, he just pours forth views he seems to pick up from elsewhere. I'd much prefer a critical engagement with what RPW presents.
PS. Thanks, aaall, for the reminder about the aged war criminal. Chile was, of course, but one place where the US applied its usual modus operandi for dealing with leftist governments
Anonymous,
I was answering this part, which makes my comment very relevant:
But these “explanations,” although charming, are not really explanations at all.
I see however after making my comment that Prof. Wolff did address Smith's explanation for profit, as the following sentence in the above quote shows.
Smith tells us that the prudent entrepreneur is unwilling to venture his capital without a return...
So, an error on my part as that covers the part in the ellipsis.
As for my other comment, that was aaall's fault because he strayed off-topic which made me stray off-topic. I think that the discussion about why profit exists is one of the most interesting questions in economics so it would have been better if aaall had commented on that part of my comment.
On Natural Price 2
Thesis1: The natural price of of a commodity is not determined primarily by its labour inputs (or its labour inputs plus the landlord’s or capitalists profits ) : It is determined in a capitalist system a) by the background demand and b) by the costs of producing it at a profit to *meet* that demand (which of course includes labour inputs). The demand is determined in turn by the prevailing technology and the relative utility of the product (as compared to similar products) *given* that technology. But the (relative) utility of the product is itself a function of consumer demand. If we did not like watching shows and movies, neither video-cassettes nor DVDS would ever have commanded a market. And if we did not care about convenience, better definition etc, DVDs (and now Netflix) would not be at a premium.
Thesis 2: Anything like a Labour Theory of Value (construed as natural price) is only adequate
a) in a technologically stable society where the background demand for most products is reasonably constant,
or
b) as a ‘snapshot’ analysis of value in a technologically dynamic society.
On ‘Das Adam Smith Problem’, Sentiment and Self-Interest.
Smith does not assume that people are entirely self interested or that rationality consists in enlightened self-interest . He assumes that people operate in a a fairly self-interested and prudentially rational way *given the constraints of morality*. It is because we have a moral sense that constrains us (to some extent) from doing one another down, that the competitive market does not degenerate into a war of all against all. You can read him as responding to Mandeville:
Vice is beneficial found
When its by justice lopped and bound
For both Smith and Hume. a vice isn’t really a vice if is in fact beneficial. (A taste for luxury for both Hume and Smith, is no bad thing.) Hume: ‘A virtue is a mental action or quality useful or agreeable to the person himself or to others’ [quoting from memory] . Hence if a trait is really useful or agreeable, it isn’t a vice.
The lopping and binding of vice isn’t just something imposed from the outside by the state or by ‘cunning politicians’. It comes partly from *within* – from the constraints we impose on ourselves as (imperfectly) moral beings. Though we don’t generally go so far as lopping our natural selfishness is (to some extent) *bound* and restrained by our by inbuilt moral sense.
This I think is the solution to the supposed ‘Das Adam Smith Problem” (How to reconcile the sentimentalist Smith of ‘A Theory of the Moral Sentiments* with the apparently egoistic Smith of ‘The Wealth of Nations’. ) It is also true of course that *families* considered as collective agent can be pretty selfish *not because the members of those families are themselves selfish but because they care a lot more about the other family members that they care about anyone else. Walter White in Breaking Bad initially claims that he got in to drug-dealing and gangsterism for the sake of his family, though he later admits he was doing it because of he liked it. But there are plenty of fathers and mothers who are fairly ruthless in business out of genuine concern of their offspring.
Neglecting the ‘givens’: Wolff on Self-interest and Natural Price.
But – and here I am criticising Professor Wolff – both here and in his account of ‘Natural Price’ he neglects the ‘givens’. It is only *given* a constant background demand for a product that its natural price is determined by labour plus profits plus rents. It is only *given* a background set of moral constraints that self-interest (according to Smith) produces generally beneficial effects. Take away the background demand and a commodity’s natural price can drop away to nothing whatever the labour that went into it. Take away the constraints of morality and the invisible hand will cease to operate in a beneficial manner, leading perhaps to war of all against all.
Post a Comment